what did Gödel believe in? The combined rules of reason, logic, and maths. Particular beliefs being consequences of applications of those rules. — tim wood
Gödel was a mathematical realist, a Platonist. He believed that what makes mathematics true is that it's descriptive—not of empirical reality, of course, but of an abstract reality. Mathematical intuition is something analogous to a kind of sense perception. — Rebecca Goldstein
Would you allow an edit to, "Truth is the seeming adequacy of thought to apparent being"?
Keeping in mind you have ruled out adequacy
Maybe he just felt that he was spending too much time on TPF and made a strong decision to leave. — Leontiskos
One particular member began editing their posts to remove everything they had written, because they'd decided they didn't want to be a member of TPF any more. When I asked about it privately they asked me to delete their account and blank their posts in one fell swoop. — Jamal
Mystery member posted a new discussion that consisted of a book title, a link to the book, and basically nothing else except for some words to the effect of "here is a book" (not even anything concerning the book's content). I deleted it for low quality and neglected to tell mystery member why I did so. Mystery member began self-erasing, and the rest is history. — Jamal
Deleted User
0
This user has been deleted and all their posts removed. — Deleted User
Does this systemic inquiry serve a practical purpose? Or is it more like Sudoku?Rather than representing failures of reasoning, these ungrounded foundations serve as necessary conditions that make systematic inquiry possible. — Moliere
That's from experience. Chairs were made by people for people to sit on and pencils were made by people for people to write with: we've known these things from early childhood. A tentacled alien would not guess how to use them. As for questioning the existence of such mundane objects, Virtual Reality and holography have brought doubt back into play.We often perform actions without hesitation, such as sitting on a chair or picking up a pencil, without questioning the existence of either. — Moliere
And yet, we can be wrong about those things. When the pencil point breaks, we fail to write; when a chair breaks, we fall down with a painful thump; when the ground is quicksand, we sink and suffocate to death. Cavemen, whose language consisted of gestures and vocalizations knew enough to test the reliability of physical objects by simple physical means.For instance, the certainty that the ground will support us when we walk is a nonlinguistic hinge that enables movement without hesitation. Similarly, our unthinking confidence that objects will behave predictably, that chairs will hold our weight, that pencils will mark paper, represents this bedrock level of certainty. — Moliere
And that makes them dangerous, because of the exceptions, gaps, biases, delusion, misinterpretation and incorrect information. Much worse, our "language games" include fiction, deception, mis- and dis-information, which are all too easily internalized as foundational. Thus cultures become interwoven with false certainties and civilizations collapse.Unlike nonlinguistic hinges, these can be spoken and seem propositional, yet they resist the usual patterns of justification and doubt. — Moliere
Bedrock is not tested with logic; it's tested with a drill. It doesn't need justification, it just needs to be hard. Only direct testing can justify non-linguistic certainty and only practice can justify linguistic certainty.Traditional approaches to knowledge often assume that proper justification requires tracing claims back to secure foundations that are themselves justified. This assumption generates the classical problem of infinite regress: any attempt to justify foundational elements through further reasoning creates an endless chain of justification that never reaches secure ground. — Moliere
I think acknowledging its failures and limitations improves cohesion of thought.Rather than representing failures or limitations, these unjustified foundations function as enabling conditions that make coherent thought and practice possible. — Moliere
To what end? This is a sincere question: What is it you hope to learn or achieve?By recognizing this necessity, we can develop more nuanced approaches to foundational questions in epistemology, philosophy of mathematics, and potentially other domains where the relationship between systematic inquiry and its enabling conditions remains philosophically significant. — Moliere
.Both thinkers uncover fundamental limits to internal justification: Wittgenstein shows that epistemic systems rest on unjustified certainties embedded in our form of life, while Gödel proves that mathematical systems require axioms that cannot be demonstrated within the system itself […] Both reveal that the search for completely self-grounding systems is not merely difficult but misconceived
implications for understanding certainty and knowledge… we can develop more nuanced approaches to foundational questions in epistemology, philosophy of mathematics, and potentially other domains where the relationship between systematic inquiry and its enabling conditions remains philosophically significant.
From: https://www.prospectmagazine.co.uk/regulars/55561/wittgensteins-forgotten-lesson‘Philosophy is not a theory but an activity.’ It strives, not after scientific truth, but after conceptual clarity.
In On Certainty, Wittgenstein introduces the idea of hinges as certainties that ground our epistemic practices. While Wittgenstein never explicitly distinguishes types of hinges, his examples suggest a distinction between non-linguistic and linguistic varieties, revealing different levels of fundamental certainties.
Non-linguistic hinges represent the most basic level of certainty,bedrock assumptions that ground our actions and interactions with the world. These are not expressed as propositions subject to justification or doubt but embodied in unreflective action.
110. But the end is not an ungrounded presupposition: it is an ungrounded way of acting.
166. The difficulty is to realize the groundlessness of our believing.
Wittgenstein breaks with traditional epistemology here. Rather than viewing these certainties as beliefs requiring justification, he recognizes them as the ungrounded ground that makes justification itself possible. He notes, "There is no why. I simply do not. This is how I act" (OC 148). Doubting these hinges would collapse the very framework within which doubt makes sense, like attempting to saw off the branch on which one sits.
: https://www.academia.edu/19857441/Wittgenstein_on_Faith_and_Reason_The_Influence_of_Newman… ‘rational support’ in question, being inherently local in this way, is not really bona fide rational support at all, in virtue of being ultimately groundless. Wittgenstein was certainly alert to this worry, writing that the “difficulty is to realise the groundlessness of our believing.” (OC, §166) On his view the regress of reasons comes to an end, but it does not come to end with further reasons of a special foundational sort as we were expecting. Instead, when we reach bedrock we discover only a rationally groundless “animal” commitment (OC, §359), a kind of “primitive” trust (OC, §475)
475. I want to regard man here as an animal; as a primitive being to which one grants instinct but not ratiocination. As a creature in a primitive state. Any logic good enough for a primitive means of communication needs no apology from us. Language did not emerge from some kind of ratiocination [Raisonnement].
A main source of our failure to understand is that we don’t have an overview of the use of our words. - Our grammar is deficient in surveyability. A surveyable representation produces precisely that kind of understanding which consists in ‘seeing connections’. Hence the importance of finding and inventing intermediate links.
The concept of a surveyable representation is of fundamental significance for us. It characterizes the way we represent things, how we look at matters. (Is this a ‘Weltanschauung’?)
To what end? This is a sincere question: What is it you hope to learn or achieve? — Vera Mont
Thank you for this well-presented OP. While I agree that Godel’s incompleteness theorems can lend themselves to the assumption of groundless grounds akin to Wittgenstein ‘hinges’, I don’t believe Godel would have been comfortable with such a relativistic, pragmatist conclusion. He considered himself a mathematical platonist. As Roger Penrose says about Godel:
Godel, himself, was a very strong Platonist…
The notion of mathematical truth goes beyond the whole concept of formalism. There is something absolute and "God-given' about mathematical truth. This is what mathematical Platonism, as discussed at the end of the last chapter, is about. Any particular formal system has a provisional and 'man-made' quality about it. Such systems indeed have very valuable roles to play in mathematical discussions, but they can supply only a partial (or approximate) guide to truth. Real mathematical truth goes beyond mere manmade constructions. (The Emperor’s New Mind) — Joshs
Yes, that's the part I didn't get: 'ungrounded foundations' seemed to me a contradiction in terms. I assumed unquestioned assumptions were formed either through empirical testing or specialized faith.By demonstrating that both knowledge and mathematics depend on unprovable starting points, the paper reveals a universal idea, viz., that our systems of understanding require ungrounded foundations to function. — Sam26
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.