• Sam26
    2.8k
    Everything is about objectivity and subjectivity, actually. It's not merely a psychological issue, but simply logical. We can easily understand subjectivity as someone's (or some things) point of view and objectivity as "a view without a viewpoint". To put this into a logical and mathematical context makes it a bit different. Here both Gödel and Wittgenstein are extremely useful.

    In logic and math a true statement that is objective can be computed and ought to be provable. Yet when it's subjective, this isn't so: something subjective refers to itself.

    Do note the self-referential aspect Gödel's incompleteness theorems, even if Gödel smartly avoids direct circular reference of Russell's Paradox. Yet I would argue that Wittgenstein observes this even in the Tractatus Logicus Philosophicus as he thinks about Russell's paradox:
    ssu

    Thank you for the thought-provoking response. Your subjective-objective distinction, self-referentiality, and the market pricing example adds to the discussion, and they challenge my claim about ungrounded foundations. Let me see if I can clarify my argument and explore the points you raise.

    You rightly emphasize the subjective-objective distinction in the context of Wittgenstein’s hinges and Gödel’s incompleteness theorems, framing subjectivity as tied to self-referentiality and objectivity as a “view without a viewpoint.” I find this interesting, particularly your point that objective truths in logic and math are typically computable and provable, while subjective ones involve self-reference, evading such formalization. Your reference to Wittgenstein’s Tractatus (3.332–3.333) and his solution to Russell’s paradox is spot-on: Wittgenstein identifies self-referentiality as a source of logical trouble, arguing that propositions or functions cannot contain themselves. This insight resonates with Gödel’s incompleteness theorems, which, as you note, cleverly navigate self-referentiality (e.g., the statement “This statement is unprovable in the system”) without falling into the traps of Russell’s paradox.

    Here I think it's very important to understand just what is objective and what is subjective in this context. An objective model can is true when it models reality correctly and can be written as a function like y = F(x). But what then would be a subjective model, that couldn't be put into the above objective mold?

    Let's take one example. Let's assume that the market pricing mechanism is dependent on the aggregate actions of all market participants. This obviously is true: trade at some price happens only when there is at least one participant willing to sell at the price and at least one willing to buy with the similar price. At first this looks quite objective and we can write as a mathematical function like y = F(X). But then, if we want to use this model, let's say to forecast what prices are going to be in the future and then participate in the market, this isn't anymore an objective function. Now actually the function is defining itself, which as Wittgenstein observed, cannot contain itself. Us using the function is self-referential, because the model is the aggregate of all market participants actions, including us. How are we deciding our actions? Because of the function itself.
    ssu

    Your market pricing example is an interesting example of how self-referentiality complicates objective modeling. When a model of market prices incorporates the actions of everyone, including the modeler’s own decisions based on the model, it becomes self-referential, undermining objectivity. This aligns with Wittgenstein’s thinking in that certain propositions (or models) cannot contain themselves without losing their coherence. It also echoes my paper’s broader point: systems of thought, whether epistemic or mathematical, often rely on foundational elements that resist internal justification. In your market e.g., the “hinge” might be the assumption that prices reflect aggregate behavior, but using the model to act within the market introduces a self-referential loop that defies objective grounding (if I understand what you're saying), which is akin to the unprovable truths in Gödel’s systems or the unquestioned certainties in Wittgenstein’s hinges.

    However, I should clarify the paper’s claim about “ungrounded foundations” in light of your critique that not all systematic thought lacks grounded foundations. My paper argues that both Wittgenstein’s hinges and Gödel’s incompleteness reveal a structural necessity: systematic thought (in sufficiently complex epistemic or mathematical systems) requires foundational elements that cannot be justified within the system itself. This doesn’t mean all foundations are ungrounded in an absolute sense, but that their grounding lies outside the system’s internal justificatory framework. For Wittgenstein, hinges are grounded in our “form of life,” i.e., in our shared practices and interactions with reality, but they resist justification through argument or evidence within the epistemic system they support. For Gödel, axioms (like those of Peano arithmetic) are grounded in their mathematical fruitfulness or intuitive plausibility, but they cannot be proven within the system they define. The “ungrounded” part refers to this internal limit, not a denial of external grounding (e.g., in practice, intuition, or objective reality for Gödel’s Platonism).

    If I understand correctly what you mean by grounded / ungrounded foundations, I would say it differently: Not all systematic thought can be brought back to grounded foundations. Usually we can use axiomatic systems and get an objective model, but not always.

    Just as there is also Gödel's completeness theorem, that theorem doesn't collide with the two incompleteness theorems.
    ssu

    Your point, that “not all systematic thought can be brought back to grounded foundations,” is a helpful perspective, but I’d argue it complements rather than contradicts the my claim. The paper doesn’t assert that all thought lacks grounded foundations, but that sufficiently complex systems (epistemic or mathematical) require ungrounded foundations within their own justificatory scope. Simpler systems, like those covered by Gödel’s completeness theorem or basic linguistic practices, may achieve internal grounding, but that the parallel with Wittgenstein and Gödel emerges in domains where complexity has limits, necessitating external or unprovable foundations.

    Your market example actually strengthens my point. The self-referential nature of the pricing model mirrors the way hinges and unprovable statements function as enabling conditions that cannot be fully justified within the system. Just as a market participant’s actions disrupt the objectivity of the pricing function, hinges and axioms enable systematic thought by standing outside the system’s justificatory reach. This suggests that the subjective-objective interplay you highlight is not just a logical issue but a structural feature of how systems, whether markets, math, or knowledge, must be organized.

    Finally, your insights about self-referentiality and the subjective-objective distinction enrich the paper’s framework, and your market example vividly illustrates the challenges of grounding complex systems. While Gödel’s completeness theorem reminds us that not all systems face incompleteness, the parallel with Wittgenstein’s hinges holds for systems where internal justification hits a limit, revealing the necessity of ungrounded foundations.
  • ssu
    9.5k
    Thank you for one of the best replies I've ever gotten in this Forum. It's really great when somebody understands my points. Here are some comments that hopefully forward this good discussion.

    You rightly emphasize the subjective-objective distinction in the context of Wittgenstein’s hinges and Gödel’s incompleteness theorems, framing subjectivity as tied to self-referentiality and objectivity as a “view without a viewpoint.” I find this interesting, particularly your point that objective truths in logic and math are typically computable and provable, while subjective ones involve self-reference, evading such formalization. Your reference to Wittgenstein’s Tractatus (3.332–3.333) and his solution to Russell’s paradox is spot-on: Wittgenstein identifies self-referentiality as a source of logical trouble, arguing that propositions or functions cannot contain themselves. This insight resonates with Gödel’s incompleteness theorems, which, as you note, cleverly navigate self-referentiality (e.g., the statement “This statement is unprovable in the system”) without falling into the traps of Russell’s paradox.Sam26
    There's one Holy Grail there if one could make it a true mathematical theorem: if that "objective truths in logic and math are typically computable and provable, while subjective ones involve self-reference, evading such formalization" could be made into "objective truths in logic and math are all computable and provable, if there isn't self-reference that leads to subjectivity". Or something like that.

    This leads to understanding that there's also true but uncomputable math and we cannot just assume objectivity to compute them. And that we do have to understand that in some occasions, the best models would be uncomputable.

    Because look at just what we have now for a definition of computation: the Church-Turing thesis. And what does that basically tell us? Basically (and not rigorously defined) that computation is something that a Turing Machine can do. Which means that something that is uncomputable is something that a Turing Machine cannot do. And not that this isn't a theorem, just a thesis. The Church-Turing thesis is said to be unprovable or basically undecidable. And this is because a direct proof and computation are so close to each other.

    The dichotomy of the subjective and the objective and Wittgenstein's remarks could really here help. It's worth mentioning that when Alan Turing and Wittgenstein met, they simply didn't understand each other. Wittgenstein say the paradox in Alan Turings undecidability result, yet as you noted that just like with Gödel's Incompleteness theorems, the example of the Turing Machine doesn't end up in a paradox. However, Wittgenstein does have an important point.

    In your market e.g., the “hinge” might be the assumption that prices reflect aggregate behavior, but using the model to act within the market introduces a self-referential loop that defies objective grounding (if I understand what you're saying), which is akin to the unprovable truths in Gödel’s systems or the unquestioned certainties in Wittgenstein’s hinges.Sam26
    Yes, once you are an acting part of a universe you are trying to model, the problem arises. Many times when you don't notice the problem, you get to a problem of infinite regress. Yet do notice that self-referential loops can get to a "objective grounding". If we have something like a self-fulfilling prophecy, that can indeed be modeled and computed.

    Your point, that “not all systematic thought can be brought back to grounded foundations,” is a helpful perspective, but I’d argue it complements rather than contradicts the my claim.Sam26
    I agree. The uncomputable are really special occasions to the norm. At least when we try to make objective scientific models.

    The paper doesn’t assert that all thought lacks grounded foundations, but that sufficiently complex systems (epistemic or mathematical) require ungrounded foundations within their own justificatory scope. Simpler systems, like those covered by Gödel’s completeness theorem or basic linguistic practices, may achieve internal grounding, but that the parallel with Wittgenstein and Gödel emerges in domains where complexity has limits, necessitating external or unprovable foundations.Sam26
    Yes, exactly. There isn't any problem with having Gödel's completeness theorem and incompleteness theorems being true at the same time.

    But let's think about just what is meant by "ungrounded foundations". Just what do we mean by this is important. In my opinion, with grounded foundations we go back to the way that an algorithm works: follow these foundations, and you can make correct model / compute the correct answer. Yet if in the foundations there is the aspect of subjectivity, all hell is loose. If the order or step would be "Here you decide what ice cream you like" it's not anymore an objective truth as it needs that subjective decision. Or the classic instruction of "Do something else not written in these instructions", which is a command that a computer cannot follow as it isn't itself a subject capable of making subjective decisions.

    I think the objectivity/subjectivity dichotomy would be an interesting way to look at this problem. I remember last year we had a good thread about , where people went through professor Noson S. Yanofsky's interesting paper True but Unprovable and the PF thread was Mathematical truth is not orderly but highly chaotic. Perhaps then the subjective / objective issue wasn't at the center stage, but it really puts the issue back to simple logic.

    Anyway, I hope these have been useful comments to you.
  • Sam26
    2.8k
    Thank you for one of the best replies I've ever gotten in this Forum. It's really great when somebody understands my points. Here are some comments that hopefully forward this good discussion.ssu

    Thanks @ssu for the compliment. There are some really interesting ideas to pursue in these posts, especially as they relate to my interest in epistemology. I'm not a mathematician, but I did manage to see a connection between Wittgenstein and Godel. I've been trying to find other writings that've made a similar connection, but I haven't been able to find anything.

    I have to move on to answering some of the other replies to my paper, but your responses were interesting.
  • Moliere
    5.8k
    Great essay @Sam26, and I found your above responses elucidating.

    I can see the structural parallel. There's a part of me that still wonders: Why this particular set of parallels? My first guess is that in two disciplines in which complicated thought is required we find a common between Godel and Wittgenstein, and that particular combination is persuasive of a larger structure in thinking that must be -- namely that there will be truths that are not grounded at the same level within any sufficiently "complicated"* body of -- knowledge?

    *Whatever that is cached out as

    I can see the analogy, but it's the part that I think could really sell the argument home -- not just a strong analogy, but even a reason to bring these people together due to the structure of thought, or something like that. Somehow strengthening the tie between the two examples.

    Still, I say that in an attempt to be helpful, and your essay far surpasses my little comments on it. Thanks for your submission!
  • Sam26
    2.8k
    I can see the structural parallel. There's a part of me that still wonders: Why this particular set of parallels? My first guess is that in two disciplines in which complicated thought is required we find a common between Godel and Wittgenstein, and that particular combination is persuasive of a larger structure in thinking that must be -- namely that there will be truths that are not grounded at the same level within any sufficiently "complicated"* body of -- knowledge?

    *Whatever that is cached out as

    I can see the analogy, but it's the part that I think could really sell the argument home -- not just a strong analogy, but even a reason to bring these people together due to the structure of thought, or something like that. Somehow strengthening the tie between the two examples.

    Still, I say that in an attempt to be helpful, and your essay far surpasses my little comments on it. Thanks for your submission!
    Moliere


    Both Wittgenstein and Gödel were investigating questions related to completeness. Wittgenstein was asking whether epistemic practices could be completely self-justifying, and Gödel was asking whether formal systems could be completely self-proving. Both men discovered that the answer was no, and both showed that this isn’t a defect to be solved but a structural necessity. These ideas solve the problem of infinite regression and the problem of circularity.

    The "why these two" question has a deeper answer, viz., they represent the most rigorous investigations into foundational questions in their respective domains, and it’s during the same historical period. Wittgenstein was examining the foundations of ordinary knowledge and language, while Gödel was examining the foundations of the most rigorous knowledge we possess (mathematics). That they independently discovered analogous structural limits suggests this isn't domain-specific but reveals something about the structure of systematic thought itself.

    As far as I can tell, no one else has made this connection, but who knows? The paper demonstrates this isn’t just about “complicated” systems needing ungrounded elements, but about the logical structure of any system that strives for internal coherence. Even simple systems, if they’re to be complete and self-justifying, will encounter such limits.

    The Wittgenstein-Gödel parallel reveals a universal logical constraint, viz., any systematic framework that attempts to ground all its statements internally will necessarily rely on elements that lie beyond its internal capacity for justification. The parallel is compelling precisely because it shows this constraint operating across the most fundamental domains of human understanding.
  • Amity
    5.8k
    Still, I say that in an attempt to be helpful, and your essay far surpasses my little comments on it. Thanks for your submission!Moliere

    As far as I am concerned, no comments on this submission are 'little'. The essay is undoubtedly substantial and received a great deal of interest from certain posters. Not surprising given the attraction, sometimes an obsession, with the name 'Wittgenstein', his importance and influence in 20th century, Western Philosophy.

    It stood out as the thickest text and, yes, it was indeed an academic paper. Specialist and exclusive.
    It stands at the extreme end of the spectrum of 'philosophy writing'.

    The challenge being met for this June event included 13 pieces of diverse creations. Thought-provoking.
    Comments, replies and responses varied accordingly. To the sense and sensitivity of the subject.
    As far as able to read and understand by questioning. Or enjoying the seeming simplicity.

    For this essay, both Vera and myself offered responses:
    Vera: (20 days ago)
    https://thephilosophyforum.com/discussion/comment/993677
    Mine: (in 2 parts, 16 days ago)
    https://thephilosophyforum.com/discussion/comment/994486
    https://thephilosophyforum.com/discussion/comment/994488

    Sam's response to Vera engaged only with her final question. The response pertinent to his aims:
    https://thephilosophyforum.com/discussion/comment/994973

    To what end? This is a sincere question: What is it you hope to learn or achieve?
    — Vera Mont

    The paper explores why we can know things at all by connecting two big ideas: Wittgenstein’s notion that our knowledge rests on unquestioned "hinges" (like assuming the ground will hold when we walk) and Gödel’s discovery that even math has true statements it can’t prove within its own rules.
    Sam26

    As someone who only studied W. briefly, a long time ago, I spent time and energy attempting a response. Given that I could see only a wall of incomprehensible gobble-de-gook, I did my best to connect. It was exhausting. However, so far, no response.

    In my original reply, I didn't include this. From the penultimate paragraph of the conclusion:
    Rather than viewing these limits as philosophical problems requiring solutions, this analysis suggests embracing them as structural necessities that make knowledge possible.Moliere

    In my notes, exclamation and question marks surround this. For me, it sounds more like a machine than a human. As do many of the detached repetitions.

    14 days ago:
    I have to move on to answering some of the other replies to my paper, but your responses were interesting.Sam26

    No further answers to the other replies were given. Instead:

    13 days ago: https://thephilosophyforum.com/discussion/comment/995416
    I decided to put my paper in this thread where it belongs. The paper tends to be a bit more precise than my general comments in this thread and elsewhere, which is why it's important to write down one's thoughts using more precise language. The area where my paper falls short is in not responding to potential criticisms. — Sam26

    The thread, started by Sam26, 5 years ago - An Analysis of "On Certainty".
    https://thephilosophyforum.com/discussion/8443/an-analysis-of-on-certainty/p1

    The essay, then, is based on a body of lengthy, analytical work. Theory-driven.
    Unlike many of the others who are arguably more refreshing and human. Unique with a spirit of creativity and engaging. Not exclusive. Or sounding like AI with its dry, authoritative tone.

    As far as I can tell, no one else has made this connection, but who knows? The paper demonstrates this isn’t just about “complicated” systems needing ungrounded elements, but about the logical structure of any system that strives for internal coherence. Even simple systems, if they’re to be complete and self-justifying, will encounter such limits.Sam26

    The connection could easily have been made by AI. Indeed, any author can now claim a 'new' find after using a prompt and conversing with AI.

    This is not to suggest that the author relied on such. It is clear that he has given his all to the project.
    This is what many think philosophy is all about.
    I hope that this event has shown otherwise. It can be this and much, much more.
  • Sam26
    2.8k
    The connection could easily have been made by AI. Indeed, any author can now claim a 'new' find after using a prompt and conversing with AI.

    This is not to suggest that the author relied on such. It is clear that he has given his all to the project.
    This is what many think philosophy is all about.
    I hope that this event has shown otherwise. It can be this and much, much more.
    Amity

    I don't think AI could have made such a connection. I made this connection more than a year ago, possibly longer, and the AI available at the time surely couldn't have made the connection between Wittgenstein and Godel.
  • Michael
    16.2k
    @Sam26

    It's worth noting that Wittgenstein disagreed with Gödel's incompleteness theorem (although apparently he misunderstood it).

    From Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics:

    I imagine someone asking my advice; he says: "I have constructed a proposition (I will use 'P' to designate it) in Russell's symbolism, and by means of certain definitions and transformations it can be so interpreted that it says: 'P is not provable in Russell's system'. Must I not say that this proposition on the one hand is true, and on the other hand unprovable? For suppose it were false; then it is true that it is provable. And that surely cannot be! And if it is proved, then it is proved that it is not provable. Thus it can only be true, but unprovable." Just as we can ask, " 'Provable' in what system?," so we must also ask, "'True' in what system?" "True in Russell's system" means, as was said, proved in Russell's system, and "false" in Russell's system means the opposite has been proved in Russell's system.—Now, what does your "suppose it is false" mean? In the Russell sense it means, "suppose the opposite is proved in Russell's system"; if that is your assumption you will now presumably give up the interpretation that it is unprovable. And by "this interpretation" I understand the translation into this English sentence.—If you assume that the proposition is provable in Russell's system, that means it is true in the Russell sense, and the interpretation "P is not provable" again has to be given up. If you assume that the proposition is true in the Russell sense, the same thing follows. Further: if the proposition is supposed to be false in some other than the Russell sense, then it does not contradict this for it to be proved in Russell's system. (What is called "losing" in chess may constitute winning in another game.)
  • Sam26
    2.8k
    It's worth noting that Wittgenstein disagreed with Gödel's incompleteness theorem (although apparently because he misunderstood it).

    From Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics:

    I imagine someone asking my advice; he says: "I have constructed a proposition (I will use 'P' to designate it) in Russell's symbolism, and by means of certain definitions and transformations it can be so interpreted that it says: 'P is not provable in Russell's system'. Must I not say that this proposition on the one hand is true, and on the other hand unprovable? For suppose it were false; then it is true that it is provable. And that surely cannot be! And if it is proved, then it is proved that it is not provable. Thus it can only be true, but unprovable." Just as we can ask, " 'Provable' in what system?," so we must also ask, "'True' in what system?" "True in Russell's system" means, as was said, proved in Russell's system, and "false" in Russell's system means the opposite has been proved in Russell's system.—Now, what does your "suppose it is false" mean? In the Russell sense it means, "suppose the opposite is proved in Russell's system"; if that is your assumption you will now presumably give up the interpretation that it is unprovable. And by "this interpretation" I understand the translation into this English sentence.—If you assume that the proposition is provable in Russell's system, that means it is true in the Russell sense, and the interpretation "P is not provable" again has to be given up. If you assume that the proposition is true in the Russell sense, the same thing follows. Further: if the proposition is supposed to be false in some other than the Russell sense, then it does not contradict this for it to be proved in Russell's system. (What is called "losing" in chess may constitute winning in another game.)
    Michael

    Wittgenstein was skeptical of Gödel’s theorem, and it seems that the disagreement, as far as I understand, was largely due to what appears to be a misunderstanding of the distinction between provability within a system and truth in the standard interpretation.

    However, the structural parallel is valid regardless of Wittgenstein’s views of Gödel. I’m not claiming that Wittgenstein endorsed this connection. I’m just making an independent philosophical observation about structural similarities in foundational limits.

    One could say that Wittgenstein’s objection supports my broader point, viz., his insistence that we must ask “True in what system?” and “Provable in what system?” which seems to support the idea that systematic frameworks require external grounding. He argues that truth and provability are always relative to a particular system, and this aligns with my argument about the necessity of external foundations.

    Regardless of how this is interpreted, my paper shows that they were both concerned with the same foundational question, i.e., how do systematic frameworks relate to what lies outside them?

    Thanks for the reply.
  • Amity
    5.8k
    I don't think AI could have made such a connection. I made this connection more than a year ago, possibly longer, and the AI available at the time surely couldn't have made the connection between Wittgenstein and Godel.Sam26

    Thank you for your thoughts re the use of AI.

    I didn't realise that you had previously made the connection, and argued for this before.
    Did you publish anywhere? There's no reference to this effect.

    The essays I thought were to be freshly spun.
    6) Entries must not be previously available online, or in print form.

    The legalities don't matter much to me. You made me think...
  • Sam26
    2.8k
    No, I haven't published, but if you go back and look at my thread 'On Certainty', you'll see that I mentioned this about a year ago.

    I don't always respond to every challenge or question because I just don't have the time. Right now, I'm working on a book on NDEs, so that occupies my time.
  • Amity
    5.8k
    if you go back and look at my thread 'On Certainty', you'll see that I mentioned this about a year ago.Sam26

    Ah, OK. I'm not that concerned about the first mention. :smile:

    I don't always respond to every challenge or question because I just don't have the time. Right now, I'm working on a book on NDEs, so that occupies my time.Sam26

    Understood.
  • Moliere
    5.8k
    The "why these two" question has a deeper answer, viz., they represent the most rigorous investigations into foundational questions in their respective domains, and it’s during the same historical period. Wittgenstein was examining the foundations of ordinary knowledge and language, while Gödel was examining the foundations of the most rigorous knowledge we possess (mathematics). That they independently discovered analogous structural limits suggests this isn't domain-specific but reveals something about the structure of systematic thought itself.Sam26

    :up: That satisfies me, at least. Similar time periods, different areas of inquiry, similar conclusions indicate that we're dealing with something deeper than just a single thinker. Especially as the thinkers, as others have said here, don't see eye-to-eye elsewhere.
123Next
bold
italic
underline
strike
code
quote
ulist
image
url
mention
reveal
youtube
tweet
Add a Comment

Welcome to The Philosophy Forum!

Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.