Let's contrast taste with morality. That you do not eat onions is perhaps a preference you would not insist applies to everyone. That folk should not lie is presumably a preference that you and I would insist applies to everyone. That is, one of the characteristics of moral statements is that they are not only about how the speaker should act, but how everyone, in comparable circumstances, should act.
Does that mesh with your view? — Banno
Our common stock of words embodies all the distinctions men have found worth drawing, and the connexions they have found worth marketing, in the lifetimes of many generation; these surely are likely to be more numerous, more sound, since they have stood up to the long test of thee survival of the fittest, and more subtle, at least in all ordinary and reasonably practical matters, than any that you or I are likely to think up in our arm-chairs of an afternoon-the most favoured alternative method.
I'm incline to ask why this should be. Anscombe would have us, at least on a direct reading, think that it is a result of adopting Christianity. There may be something in that.our language has evolved over time and it seems possible that it has been structured in such a way that emotive responses, value judgements, and our moral sense of right and wrong are expressed in ways that seem to be descriptive, objective, or universal when they are much more evaluative, subjective, or particular — Cartesian trigger-puppets
I'm of the opinion that there is no adequate analysis of what that correspondence consists in. See https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/truth-correspondence/#9.2 (I'm less convinced by the slingshot argument).Possible facts and negative fact are not contingent upon the existence of a corresponding thing, object, or entity as a condition to be factual, but the truth (in the absolute sense) is. — Cartesian trigger-puppets
Plato, Aristotle, Descartes, Spinoza, Locke, Leibniz, Berkeley, Kant, William James, Moore, Hume, Mill, etc, all subscribed to a correspondence account of truth
— Cartesian trigger-puppets
I very much doubt that. — Wayfarer
The correspondence theory is often traced back to Aristotle’s well-known definition of truth (Metaphysics 1011b25): “To say of what is that it is not, or of what is not that it is, is false, while to say of what is that it is, and of what is not that it is not, is true”—but virtually identical formulations can be found in Plato (Cratylus 385b2, Sophist 263b).
Authors of the modern period generally convey the impression that the correspondence theory of truth is far too obvious to merit much, or any, discussion. Brief statements of some version or other can be found in almost all major writers; see e.g.: Descartes 1639, ATII 597; Spinoza, Ethics, axiom vi; Locke, Essay, 4.5.1; Leibniz, New Essays, 4.5.2; Hume, Treatise, 3.1.1; and Kant 1787, B82. Berkeley, who does not seem to offer any account of truth, is a potentially significant exception.
. . .moderns generally subscribe to a representational theory of the mind (the theory of ideas), they would seem to be ultimately committed to spelling out relations like correspondence or conformity in terms of a psycho-semantic representation relation holding between ideas, or sentential sequences of ideas (Locke’s “mental propositions”), and appropriate portions of reality, thereby effecting a merger between metaphysical and semantic versions of the correspondence theory.
The now classical formulation of a fact-based correspondence theory was foreshadowed by Hume (Treatise, 3.1.1) and Mill (Logic, 1.5.1). It appears in its canonical form early in the 20th century in Moore (1910-11, chap. 15) and Russell: “Thus a belief is true when there is a corresponding fact, and is false when there is no corresponding fact” (1912, p. 129; cf. also his 1905, 1906, 1910, and 1913).
Even philosophers whose overall views may well lead one to expect otherwise tend to agree. Kant: “The nominal definition of truth, that it is the agreement of [a cognition] with its object, is assumed as granted” (1787, B82). William James: “Truth, as any dictionary will tell you, is a property of certain of our ideas. It means their ‘agreement’, as falsity means their disagreement, with ‘reality’” (1907, p. 96). — Marian David
Plato, on the premise that truth is objective, argued thar in order to justify knowledge of true propositions they must be about real things. — Cartesian trigger-puppets
I'm of the opinion that there is no adequate analysis of what that correspondence consists in. — Banno
According to this theory (correspondence), truth consists in the agreement of our thought with reality. This view ... seems to conform rather closely to our ordinary common sense usage when we speak of truth. The flaws in the definition arise when we ask what is meant by "agreement" or "correspondence" of ideas and objects, beliefs and facts, thought and reality. In order to test the truth of an idea or belief we must presumably compare it with the reality in some sense.
1. In order to make the comparison, we must know what it is that we are comparing, namely, the belief on the one hand and the reality on the other. But if we already know the reality, why do we need to make a comparison? And if we don't know the reality, how can we make a comparison?
2. The making of the comparison is itself a fact about which we have a belief. We have to believe that the belief about the comparison is true. How do we know that our belief in this agreement is "true"? This leads to an infinite regress, leaving us with no assurance of true belief. — Randall, J. & Buchler, J. Philosophy: An Introduction. p133
Although it seems ... obvious to say, "Truth is correspondence of thought (belief, proposition) to what is actually the case", such an assertion nevertheless involves a metaphysical assumption - that there is a fact, object, or state of affairs, independent of our knowledge to which our knowledge corresponds.
"How, on your principles, could you know you have a true proposition?" ... or ... "How can you use your definition of truth, it being the correspondence between a judgment and its object, as a criterion of truth? How can you know when such correspondence actually holds?"
I cannot step outside my mind to compare a thought in it with something outside it. — Beck, L.W. & Holmes, R.L., Philosophic Inquiry, p130.
Does a true proposition correspond to a fact in the way that the color sample on the color chart corresponds to the color of the paint on the wall? No, there is certainly no resemblance between a proposition and a state-of-affairs. .
. . . it is not clear that we meet any facts in experience. We meet people, stars, chairs, and other objects, but not facts or states of affairs. And if this is so, and the objection is cogent, it tells against all correspondence theories of truth. — Hospers, J. An Introduction to Philosophical Analysis, p116.
All cognition takes place through assimilation.But there is no assimilation possible between the mind and material things, because likeness depends on sameness of quality. However, the qualities of material things are bodily accidents which cannot exist in the mind. Therefore, the mind cannot know material things. — Aquinas, Thomas, Truth, Vol. II, Qs. 10, Article 4.
Truth, it is said, consists in the agreement of cognition with its object. In consequence of this mere nominal definition, my cognition, to count as true, is supposed to agree with its object. Now I can compare the object with my cognition, however, only by cognising it. Hence my cognition is supposed to confirm itself, which is far short of being sufficient for truth. For since the object is outside me, the cognition in me, all I can ever pass judgement on is whether my cognition of the object agrees with my cognition of the object”. — Kant, 1801. The Jasche Logic, in Lectures on Logic
I think the implication of this is that material things are by their nature or in their own right unintelligible, that their intelligibility is owed to their being of a intelligible form or type. — Wayfarer
I can't see anything that supports that in the SEP article. Are there real things in Plato's philosophy? I would have thought that 'things' were only real insofar as they were instantiations of ideas. (See entry on Aquinas below). — Wayfarer
SOCRATES: But if neither is right, if it isn’t the case that everything always has every attribute simultaneously or that each thing has a being or essence privately for each person, then it is clear that things have some fixed being or essence of their own. They are not in relation to us and are not made to fluctuate by how they appear to us. They are by themselves, in relation to their own being or essence, which is theirs by nature.
HERMOGENES: I agree, Socrates.
SOCRATES: And if things are of such a nature, doesn’t the same hold of actions performed in relation to them? Or aren’t actions included in some one class of the things that are?
HERMOGENES: Of course they are.
SOCRATES: So an action’s performance accords with the action’s own nature, and not with what we believe. Suppose, for example, that we undertake to cut something. If we make the cut in whatever way we choose and with whatever tool we choose, we will not succeed in cutting. But if in each case we choose to cut in accord with the nature of cutting and being cut and with the natural tool for cutting, we’ll succeed and cut correctly. If we try to cut contrary to nature, however, we’ll be in error and accomplish nothing.
HERMOGENES: That’s my view, at least.
SOCRATES: So, again, if we undertake to burn something, our burning mustn’t accord with every belief but with the correct one—that is to say, with the one that tells us how that thing burns and is burned naturally,
and what the natural tool for burning it is?
HERMOGENES: That’s right.
SOCRATES: And the same holds of all other actions?
HERMOGENES: Certainly.
SOCRATES: Now isn’t speaking or saying one sort of action?
HERMOGENES: Yes.
SOCRATES: Then will someone speak correctly if he speaks in whatever way he believes he should speak? Or isn’t it rather the case that he will accomplish something and succeed in speaking if he says things in the natural way to say them, in the natural way for them to be said, and with the natural tool for saying them? But if he speaks in any other way he will be in error and accomplish nothing?
HERMOGENES: I believe so.
SOCRATES: Tell me this. Is there something you call speaking the truth and something you call speaking a falsehood?
HERMOGENES: Indeed, there is.
SOCRATES: Then some statements are true, while others are false?
HERMOGENES: Certainly.
SOCRATES: And those that say of the things that are that they are, are true, while those that say of the things that are that they are not, are false?
HERMOGENES: Yes — Plato
Why Ctesippus, said Euthydemus, do you think it possible to tell lies?
Good heavens yes, he said, I should be raving if I didn’t.
When one speaks the thing one is talking about, or when one does not speak it?
When one speaks it, he said.
So that if he speaks this thing, he speaks no other one of things that are except the very one he speaks?
Of course, said Ctesippus.
And the thing he speaks is one of those that are, distinct from the rest?
Certainly.
Then the person speaking that thing speaks what is, he said.
Yes.
But surely the person who speaks what is and things that are speaks the truth – so that Dionysodorus, if he speaks things that are, speaks the truth and tells no
lies about you.
Yes, said Ctesippus, but a person who speaks these things, Euthydemus, does not speak things that are.
And Euthydemus said, But the things that are not surely [are not], no?
No, they [are not].
Then there is nowhere that the things that are not are?
Nowhere.
Then there is no possibility that any person whatsoever could do anything to the things that are not so as to make them be when they are nowhere?
It seems unlikely to me, Ctesippus said.
Well then, when the orators speak to the people, do they do nothing?
No, they do something, he said.
Then if they do something, they also make something?
Yes.
Speaking, then, is doing and making?
He agreed.
Then nobody speaks things that are not, since he would then be making something, and you have admitted that no one is capable of making something that is not. So according to your own statement, nobody tells lies. — Plato
“Theaetetus sits” (a) The true statement says things that are, as they are about you [i.e. about Theaetetus] (263 B4 f). “Theaetetus flies”
(b) The false statement says things different from the things that are (263 B7).
(c) Accordingly it says things that are not as things that are (263 B9).
(d) But things that are different from things that are about you (263 Bn).
(e) For we said that about everything there are many things that are and also many that are-not (263 B11 f). — Seligman P.
Yes, h. sapiens is an eusocial primate species, which, I think, grounds our 'moral instincts (tendencies)' in our socio-biology and develops, or becomes more nuanced, as our social ecologies become more complex and accelerated.Our ancestors must have had nascent empathy to even start on this journey - how else can one raise young? And I would have thought that in tribal living being able to support each other would have strengthened survival chances. Reciprocal altruism is just as likely to have emerged ... — Tom Storm
Yes. Moral facts are, in effect, truth-makers / warrants for moral claims.Are there moral facts? — Cartesian trigger-puppets
We know moral facts by the specific moral claims for help which they warrant. A moral claim is objective (i.e. subject/pov-invariant) in so far as it is manifested by the in situ-probability that neglecting natural (species) functional defects (e.g. hunger, fear, trust) of an individual will increase and/or prolong gratuitous / net harm to, or dysfunction of, that individual's defects (e.g. starvation, terror, distrust). When it occurs, the harm caused or contributed to by neglecting a fellow human being's natural (species) functional defects is the moral fact of the matter; and, is therefore, an Is that entails what one Ought Not to do.If there are moral facts, how can we know them?
You are conflating statements with facts. Why? (The map =/= territory.) I don't think "moral statements" – normativity – when I say 'moral claim'. What am I missing by deviating from the specious ontic premises of (e.g.) "error theory"?I'm asking for an example of an objective moral fact. This would be a moral statement (e.g., genocide is wrong) that is true independent of us. — Cartesian trigger-puppets
A barefoot little girl cries alone at night on an empty street. Her distress, loneliness & defenselessness constitute a moral claim for help. That those abject conditions can increase and/or be prolonged by neglecting to help her is a moral fact recognized by SEEING (I. Murdoch, E. Levinas, P. Foot) oneself, or anyone else one cares about, in that little girl's "shoes".Do you have such an example.
E.g. Peirce & Dewey ...It's the action that counts in moral issues, as you say; It's unclear how truth relates to actions. — Banno
(re: TLP, 6.41-6.421) :up:I wonder how you interpret these passages, then. — Wayfarer
Psychiatry has, since various drugs have come to market, become the business of prescribing those drugs. The talking cure that psychiatry was supposed to be was a notorious non-success, even as it burnished its reputation and theories with self-congratulation. If you were being ironic, excellent joke!It is for them that psychiatry is a cure. — Wayfarer
I think the passage in the middle about the meaning of nouns and names is rather different in spirit from the quoted passages. — Wayfarer
This seems to indicate that issues of morality can, to begin with, be meaningfully discussed only in the context of such a moral regulatory system as religion. This points in the direction of moral relativism / moral contextualism. And that answering a question like "Is X moral?" is the same kind of question as "What are the attributes of God?" -- in the sense that like the second question, the first one as well can only be answered with a reference to a particular religious doctrine, but that beyond that, it does not apply.In traditional moral systems, it was assumed that one was subject to judgement by God, or would endure the consequences of their karma in future lives. In the absence of those regulatory systems, the question has no clear answer, as is exemplified by the diversity of responses in this thread. — Wayfarer
Such an approach becomes questionable when it comes to people who have been stigmatized or ostracized by a society.But moral judgements are first and foremost about meaning, in terms of what the facts imply for me and for other subjects. — Wayfarer
Such as gut feeling?That moral judgement requires something more than quantitative analysis? — Wayfarer
Why shouldn't different propositions have different ways of being found true or false? — Banno
All it could do is talk about itself. — Banno
Moral facts are, in effect, truth-makers / warrants for moral claims. — 180 Proof
I'm asking for an example of an objective moral fact. This would be a moral statement (e.g., genocide is wrong) that is true independent of us.
— Cartesian trigger-puppets
You are conflating statements with facts. Why? — 180 Proof
I don't think "moral statements" – normativity – when I say 'moral claim'. What am I missing by deviating from the specious ontic premises of (e.g.) "error theory"? — 180 Proof
Do you have such an example?
A barefoot little girl cries alone at night on an empty street. Her distress, loneliness & defenselessness constitute a moral claim for help. That those abject conditions can increase and/or be prolonged by neglecting to help her is a moral fact recognized by SEEING (I. Murdoch, E. Levinas, P. Foot) oneself, or anyone else one cares about, in that little girl's "shoes". — 180 Proof
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.