So because most of the time, in everyday usage, we use the word "things" instead of "beings" for inanimate objects (as a matter of fact, for any object whatsoever), this is an example of the "forgetfulness of being" of modernity? Is that really what you're arguing? — Xtrix
The really hard problem of consciousness is the problem of experience. When we think and perceive, there is a whir of information-processing, but there is also a subjective aspect. As Nagel (1974, 'What is it like to be a Bat?') has put it, there is something it is like to be a conscious organism. This subjective aspect is experience. When we see, for example, we experience visual sensations: the felt quality of redness, the experience of dark and light, the quality of depth in a visual field. Other experiences go along with perception in different modalities: the sound of a clarinet, the smell of mothballs. Then there are bodily sensations, from pains to orgasms; mental images that are conjured up internally; the felt quality of emotion, and the experience of a stream of conscious thought. What unites all of these states is that there is something it is like to be in them. All of them are states of experience.
We ourselves, as physical organisms, are part of that universe [i.e. the universe described by the natural sciences], composed of the same basic elements as everything else, and recent advances in molecular biology have greatly increased our understanding of the physical and chemical basis of life. Since our mental lives evidently depend on our existence as physical organisms, especially on the functioning of our central nervous systems, it seems natural to think that the physical sciences can in principle provide the basis for an explanation of the mental aspects of reality as well — that physics can aspire finally to be a theory of everything.
However, I believe this possibility is ruled out by the conditions that have defined the physical sciences from the beginning. The physical sciences can describe organisms like ourselves as parts of the objective spatio-temporal order – our structure and behavior in space and time – but they cannot describe the subjective experiences of such organisms or how the world appears to their different particular points of view. There can be a purely physical description of the neurophysiological processes that give rise to an experience, and also of the physical behavior that is typically associated with it, but such a description, however complete, will leave out the subjective essence of the experience – how it is from the point of view of its subject — without which it would not be a conscious experience at all.
So the physical sciences, in spite of their extraordinary success in their own domain, necessarily leave an important aspect of nature unexplained.
An impersonal, unreflective, robotic, mindless little scrap of molecular machinery is the ultimate basis of all the agency, and hence meaning, and hence consciousness, in the universe. — Daniel Dennett, Evolution and the Meanings of Life, p202-203
True, no one has pinned down what consciousness means yet as a technical notion. Hence the use of quotation marks. — Xtrix
So I am arguing is that the very element or aspect of reality which both these passages are referring to as 'what it is like' or 'the point of view of the subject' is actually 'being', and that attribute is why living creatures are called 'beings'. — Wayfarer
So I am arguing is that the very element or aspect of reality which both these passages are referring to as 'what it is like' or 'the point of view of the subject' is actually 'being', and that attribute is why living creatures are called 'beings'. In the broadest sense, 'being' is the capacity for experience, which is found in the simplest of organisms, but which reaches the plateau of self-aware, rational being in human beings. — Wayfarer
So consciousness (of any kind) is "being," which is why (as you claim) we only refer to sentient beings as "beings." But this (1) completely ignores the field of ontology and the Greek sense of being and (2) is simply subjectivizing the word. — Xtrix
Your well within the ontological distinction of "being and thinking," which has a long tradition. — Xtrix
Consciousness or mind or rationality is that which discloses meaning, which makes it possible to define, consider, or analyse anything in the first place. Yet we don't actually know what it is, just as Nagel remarks in his OP. — Wayfarer
Don't you think that the issue of the 'hard problem of consciousness' and Chalmer's argument as to why the natural sciences can't sufficiently describe the nature of experience is basically an argument about ontology? — Wayfarer
Oh, I'm sorry, then. I thought this was a philosophical discussion. I will, however, be edified in my newfound knowledge that buildings are beings. So long. — Wayfarer
For example? — Wayfarer
I never claimed this. I have said 'being' in the noun form refers to living creatures. — Wayfarer
The noun form - as in ‘a being’ - is not used in relation to insentient objects, artefacts, tools, minerals, and so on; such things are never referred to as 'beings'. — Wayfarer
The very idea of a conscious entity (a conscious, "rational" being) as sui generis and the "problem of consciousness" itself are, at bottom, taking up the tradition of substance ontology and, I would argue, presuppose the subject/object distinction. — Xtrix
The fact that you find so strange the idea of a building as a being, or a chair, or a rock, or literally anything at all, is puzzling. Unless you've managed to ignore ontology (and metaphysics) altogether. — Xtrix
Heidegger's talk of Being may sound obscure, but at least in his most famous work, Being and Time (1927), what he means by it is fairly straightforward. The Being of entities is “that on the basis of which they are already understood” by us, however implicitly and inchoately. In other words, the Being of an entity is the condition under which we can recognize it as an entity of a certain kind. For example, as we’ll soon see, it is only on the basis of forms of human practice that entities like hammers can be recognized and understood. To “forget” Being is, therefore, to ignore the conditions – forms of practice, for instance – that make it possible for us to experience things, for anything to “show up” for us. This failure of attention, Heidegger argues, is endemic in Western philosophical tradition, most strikingly in the Cartesian picture that, he maintains, nearly all philosophers since Descartes have broadly endorsed.
With its strict division between selves and the world, subjects and objects, or mind and nature, this picture sets us against the world, in effect treating it as alien to us. And it is a bad picture, since in reality, Heidegger argues, we and the world cannot, even notionally, exist without one another: “self and world” are not “two beings”, but mutually dependent. The Cartesian picture results from viewing us in an over-intellectual way – as, essentially, “thinking things” who observe objects and mentally represent them. Phenomenological attention, undistorted by theory, to “things themselves” yields a very different picture of how we relate to the world, however. We do so, not as “spectators” or “thinkers”, but “primordially” as agents, for whom things are revealed as “equipment”, as things – like hammers – that we use and which owe their identity to their place in purposive human activities, such as carpentry. The world is intelligible to us, in the first instance, as a “relational totality” of “ready-to-hand equipment”, in which each thing has significance for us through its location in this “sign-like” whole. The hammer is implicated in a whole form of life – of working, building, bringing up a family and so on. ...
This account of our being-in-the-world, Heidegger recognizes, does not do justice to the unique character of human existence: after all, animals also cope with, and to a degree understand, their environments. What is missing is the appreciation that creatures with our kind of Being (Dasein) are not only “absorbed” in everyday practices, but are able to regard their lives as an “issue” for them – to take stock of these lives and make them “their own”, by giving them sense and direction. Only when we choose to do this are our lives “authentic”, and no longer the “inauthentic” ones we lead when we allow, as we do for the most part, our practices, tastes and interests to be dictated by “Them” (Das Man), the faceless “public” that dominates in the “average everydayness” of human life. The capacity for authentically seizing hold of one’s life is intimated by Angst – an “uncanny” mood in which “everyday familiarity collapses”, so that previously entrenched convictions lose their hold. Precisely because Angst is a disturbing mood, however, people are more than ready to suppress or “flee from” it, back into the reassuring arms of “Them”.
But not all objects are subjects it would seem, unless you attribute to rocks conscious awareness, which I doubt anyone would. — Xtrix
It says that most modern analytical philosophy now doesn't recognize the distinction - which is the point I'm making! — Wayfarer
Buildings and office furniture are not 'beings'. If a building burns down - unfortunately this has happened more than a thousand times in my part of the world in the last few weeks - we don't say that the building and its contents 'died. But if it contains living beings - animals or people - then we say 'they died'. Is it strange to say that? Does saying that amount to 'ignoring ontology'? How is this 'ignoring metaphysics'? — Wayfarer
What do you make of this gloss of Heidegger's work: — Wayfarer
Note, 'our kind of Being', capitalised. What do you make of that? — Wayfarer
Anway, I've been told I'm 'peddling nonsense' a number of times in this thread already, which I think is completely untrue, but I will go and do some more reading and contemplation and will take a time out for a while. Bye. — Wayfarer
Buildings and office furniture are certainly beings. — Xtrix
It also says that ancient Greek philosophy didn’t even have separate words with which to make the distinction, which makes the whole thing seem like an oddity of theistic medieval philosophy. — Pfhorrest
Eventually, however, the concept of "existentia" ("existence") was established amongst Medieval Christian philosophers such as St. Thomas Aquinas as a technical term contrasted with "essentia" ("essence"), an abstract form of the presumed present participle of "esse" ("to be"). While essence apparently meant "what a thing is," existence meant "that a thing exists." According to Charles H. Khan, this development of the modern sense of existence occurred under the influence of Islamic philosophy, which distinguished existence (wujud) from essence (mahiat) in its radical revision of Greek ontology in light of a biblical metaphysics of creation within Islam which distinguished the created world (contingency) from God (necessity).
It also says that ancient Greek philosophy didn’t even have separate words with which to make the distinction, which makes the whole thing seem like an oddity of theistic medieval philosophy. — Pfhorrest
Islamic philosophy, which distinguished existence (wujud) from essence (mahiat) in its radical revision of Greek ontology in light of a biblical metaphysics of creation
I'm wondering how many people in this forum still see the world in this way or something similar to it. It seems to be the philosophical basis for modern science, at least since Descartes. — Xtrix
Well, that’s just not so. Maybe you’re not a native English speaker? — Wayfarer
So the human observer can't be extracted from the theory. It becomes unavoidably subjective. — Phillip Ball
So I acknowledge that buildings and office furniture ARE beings after all - and that to distinguish them, ontologically speaking, as ‘objects’ instead fails to recognise their relative temporal existence in the universe. — Possibility
Well, that’s just not so. Maybe you’re not a native English speaker? Buildings and furniture are structures and artefacts. The point is that beings are not things or objects, but are subjects of experience, which is demonstrably not the case for inanimate objects — Wayfarer
(Bold mine)Buildings and office furniture are certainly beings. No one is saying they're sentient beings. How is this hard for you to understand? Possibly because you not only ignore ontology,but you ignore me and everyone else on this thread who continually try to tell you that "being" as "conscious being" is your peculiar terminology. — Xtrix
I’m not talking about grammar or world languages. I’m talking ontology. It’s discouraging that this has to be explained, repeatedly, in a philosophy forum. — Xtrix
In my view it would mean that we’re not engaged with the world in a particular way (in this case, as “abstract thinking”). Heidegger would say something similar, only as a “present-at-hand” mode of being.
Once you’re in this mode, then a subject contemplating objects as a fundamental distinction can commence. But this is a “privative” mode- what human beings do for the most part does not involve subjects and objects at all. — Xtrix
Well reminds me of driving. When traffic is flowing smoothly we're completely unconscious of the act - the car and the driver are one. The instant something unexpected happens the driver becomes aware of driving the car. Carrying this to its logical conclusion, taking into account your other thread on the problems the world is facing, it seems that the scientific bent of the human mind, albeit only expressed in a minority but widely claimed by all, which is the quintessence of the subject-object distinction, is actually an indication that the world has broken and is now present-at-hand. It makes sense since morality, something that has been on our minds for over 2000 years, is about oughts, as if to say the world is busted and needs repair. — TheMadFool
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.