I was admitting that I may have made a mistake in my analysis of what you've been arguing. Perhaps a direct question would help.
Do you hold that universals are independent from language? — creativesoul
MU accepts unbroken as an antonym of continuous, but not as a synonym of undivided. — apokrisis
Is a discrete entity continuous within itself? — Janus
But in case you haven't noticed, definitions are usually composed of defining terms, not synonyms. Red is defined as a colour, but this does not mean that "red" and "a colour" are synonymous. — Metaphysician Undercover
I think in the classical understanding, ‘particulars’ are only considered to be real insofar as they are ‘instances’ of universals; so for example an individual is an instance of the species. In fact the sense in which individual things can be considered real is one of the basic factors behind the whole discussion. — Wayfarer
But a discrete thing is considered to be one thing separate (or at least separable) from all others. If it is composed of parts and this entails that it is not a discrete thing then it cannot be a unity, surely. — Janus
The traditional terminology for ‘discrete things’ is ‘particulars’, in distinction from ‘universals’. I think in the classical understanding, ‘particulars’ are only considered to be real insofar as they are ‘instances’ of universals; so for example an individual is an instance of the species. In fact the sense in which individual things can be considered real is one of the basic factors behind the whole discussion. I think we’re inclined nowadays to assume that individual particulars are the paradigm of what is real; this pen, that chair. But Greek philosophy was inclined to doubt that mere things, perishable as they are, ought to be considered real in their own right. — Wayfarer
If you have a division defined in terms of opposing limits, then you also get the continuous spectrum of possibility that lies between. — apokrisis
In Aristotelian logic, "substance" is given to the individual, the particular. — Metaphysician Undercover
The whole thing, such and such a form in this flesh and these bones, is Callias or Socrates; and they are different owing to their matter (for this is different), but the same in species, for the species is indivisible.
if the proper knowledge of the senses is of accidents, through forms that are individualized, the proper knowledge of intellect is of essences, through forms that are universalized. Intellectual knowledge is analogous to sense knowledge inasmuch as it demands the reception of the form of the thing which is known. But it differs from sense knowledge so far forth as it consists in the apprehension of things, not in their individuality, but in their universality.
Degrees of reality In contrast to contemporary philosophers, most 17th century philosophers held that reality comes in degrees—that some things that exist are more or less real than other things that exist. At least part of what dictates a being’s reality, according to these philosophers, is the extent to which its existence is dependent on other things: the less dependent a thing is on other things for its existence, the more real it is.
I think you're misunderstanding what realism about universals entails. — Andrew M
Here's a specific example. Aristotle defined humans as the rational animal. For arguments sake, let's suppose that rationality just is the ability to use language. So humans are the language-using animal.
Does this mean that the existence of humans is dependent on language? Obviously if there was no language, then there would be no humans per the above definition. (Just as there weren't earlier in evolutionary history.)
But it doesn't follow that being human is therefore a language construct or human creation (as if humans created themselves via definition!) Instead that language-using ability is a feature of the world as exhibited by select individuals of the animal kingdom. And it is that feature of the world that is being picked out in the definition as the essential distinguishing feature between humans and other animals.
Do you hold that universals are independent from language?
— creativesoul
I’ve explained. Universals are constraints. Constraints are causal. Causal is real.
And then language is a semiotic constraint on meaning. Language can be generalised pansemiotically to talk about the machinery of constraints in general.
So in a loose sense - one far more general than your locution hopes to imply - all universals depend on language, or rather the semiotic relation by which constraints on being develop.
Most universals of course don’t rely on human language - human socio-cultural constraints. Tables and chairs do. Constructs like masculinity do. But a horse is a horse due to genetic level information, or constraints over bioiogical development. An electron is an electron due to more fundamental symmetry constraints over material development.
So the way you pose your question fails to recognise the greater metaphysical generality of the metaphysical framework I employ. Your question only seemed direct as it depends on a far more limited notion of causality and existence. — apokrisis
There is nothing about "discrete thing", which denies that the discrete thing can be made of parts. It is a unity and a unity may have parts. — Metaphysician Undercover
That it is bounded makes it a discrete thing. It is when we look at the parts as discrete things in themselves, that we put in jeopardy the unity of the original thing.
To say that the parts are discrete things requires that we assume another principle to account for unity of the original thing. So it is by this other principle, the mereological principle, that the parts make up a whole. The nature of the mereological principle is what monists and dualists disagree on.
If we deny the need for a mereological principle we end up with apokrisis' systems approach. As a whole, or as a part, are two different ways of looking at the same thing. Whether it is related to a larger thing or to smaller things, determines whether it is a part or whether it is a whole. This denies the need for a mereological principle to account for unity, but a unity is just an arbitrary designation relative to one's perspective.
It follows that being a human is existentially contingent upon language. No language... no humans, according to that definition, anyway. Being existentially contingent upon language and being a language construct are not equivalent. — creativesoul
It follows that being a human is existentially contingent upon language. No language... no humans, according to that definition, anyway. Being existentially contingent upon language and being a language construct are not equivalent.
— creativesoul
That doesn't follow; — Janus
Aristotle defined humans as the rational animal. For arguments sake, let's suppose that rationality just is the ability to use language. So humans are the language-using animal.
Aristotle may have, according to your definition of 'rational', defined humans as the language-using animal; but this can be taken as meaning 'the animal that now uses language" and need not be taken as 'the animal that always used language' or 'the animal that always will use language". — Janus
Aristotle defined humans as the rational animal. For arguments sake, let's suppose that rationality just is the ability to use language. So humans are the language-using animal.
In other words, Aristotle may have, according to your definition of 'rational', defined humans as the language-using animal; but this can be taken as meaning 'the animal that now uses language" and need not be taken as 'the animal that always used language' or 'the animal that always will use language". — Janus
...the definition doesn't say that we became human by beginning to use language, or that we would cease to be human if language use somehow disappeared. — Janus
All your examples are of not using language. — creativesoul
From Wayfarer's article:
...Although Aristotle said that Socrates had never separated the Forms from the objects of experience, which is probably true, some of Socrates's language suggests the direction of Plato's theory. Thus, in the Euthyphro, Socrates, in asking for a definition of piety, says that he does not want to know about individual pious things, but about the "idea itself," so that he may "look upon it" and, using it "as a model [parádeigma, "paradigm" in English]," judge "that any action of yours or another's that is of that kind is pious, and if it is not that it is not" [6e, G.M.A. Grube trans., Hackett, 1986]. Plato concludes that what we "look upon" as a model, and is not an object of experience, is some other kind of real object, which has an existence elsewhere. That "elsewhere" is the "World of Forms," to which we have only had access, as the Myth of Chariot in the Phaedrus says, before birth, and which we are now only remembering.
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.