If the Humean is committed to all issues of value ultimately stemming from wholly irrational passions, then this applies just as much to all questions of truth. Hence, the foundations of reason, logic, etc. would themselves be irrational (some are indeed willing to accept this).
The second counter is to claim that all notions of goodness ultimately stem from some sort of kernal of irrational preference. [...]. — Count Timothy von Icarus
As a result, certain character traits commonly deemed virtues by the major religions of the time are deemed vices on Hume's theory. Hume calls these so-called "virtues", such as self-denial and humility, monkish virtues. Rather vehemently, he writes:
Celibacy, fasting, penance, mortification, self-denial, humility, silence, solitude, and the whole train of monkish virtues; for what reason are they everywhere rejected by men of sense, but because they serve to no manner of purpose; neither advance a man's fortune in the world, nor render him a more valuable member of society; neither qualify him for the entertainment of company, nor increase his power of self-enjoyment? We observe, on the contrary, that they cross all these desirable ends; stupify the understanding and harden the heart, obscure the fancy and sour the temper. We justly, therefore, transfer them to the opposite column, and place them in the catalogue of vices... (EPM, §9, ¶3) — https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/An_Enquiry_Concerning_the_Principles_of_Morals#Virtue_ethics
Here, it may be helpful to look back to Aristotle’s teacher, Plato. In the Republic, Plato examines the way in which an individual can become more or less a self-determining whole. We all want what is truly good for us, not what merely appears to be good, or what is said to be good by others.28 It never makes sense for us to intentionally choose what is truly worse over what is truly better. Those who claim to “prefer evil,” prefer it because they see it as “better for them.” Even Milton’s Satan must say “evil, be thou my good.”29 It would not make sense to say “evil, be thou evil for me” and then to pursue evil.xvii
For Plato, it is the “rational part of the soul” that both seeks, and is able to determine, “what is truly good.”xviii Hence, it is also the rational part of a person that is capable of ranking and ordering the passions and appetites, and only it is suited to determining the means through which they might be satisfied. A person’s thirst tells her nothing about how to pursue her anger. Her sorrow cannot tell her whether or not she should give in to her desire for sleep. Only reason has the calculating power to judge between desires and to determine which is most worthy of satisfaction.
Thus, the rational part of a person must reach downwards and shape the lower parts. For Plato, as for Aristotle and St. Thomas, we always desire things that are in some way good. We do not consciously wish evil on ourselves. The appetites and passions, however, seek only relative goods. If we are led by them, we shall stumble into evil through seeking a fractured part of the Good, its appearances, rather than the whole/absolute.30
Pace Nietzsche, this is not meant to be “the tyranny of the reason,” and the abrogation of the passions. The “just man” is not merely a special case of the “tyrannical man,” one with the proper part of the soul acting as tyrant. The just ruler focuses on what is good for the whole; the tyrant on what is good for himself (a mere part). As Plato makes clear in the Phaedrus, it is the rule of reason that will allow the passions and appetites to be most fulfilled, allowing them to get to what is truly best for them.
Whereas, if the parts of the soul are in conflict, the person will bounce randomly between different objects of desire, like a chariot whose rider is not in control of its horses, never getting to what any part of the soul would truly benefit from most. We might consider here the sex addict, who—through the tyranny of their appetites—does not enjoy even the object of their addiction as much as they would if they were properly oriented towards it. Thus, Plato can affirm the need for the rule of reason, while still speaking of the philosophers’ eros (appetitive desire) and love (passion) for goodness and truth
Hence, there is no conflict between the “well-being of having what reason knows as truly best” and the “well-being of fulfilling the passions and appetites most fully.” Such a multiplicity of goods is a contradiction in terms for Plato (and for Aristotle and St. Thomas as well). Indeed, Plato, and others following in his footsteps, such as St. Augustine, often describe the Good they pursue in highly sensuous terms. Consider St. Augustine’s prayer to God in Book X of the Confessions31:
“You called and cried out loud and shattered my deafness.
You were radiant and resplendent, you put to flight my blindness.
You were fragrant, and I drew in my breath and now pant after you.
I tasted you, and I feel but hunger and thirst for you.
You touched me, and I am set on fire to attain the peace which is yours.”
It is this desire of reason to have what is “truly best” that allows us to transcend what we already are. Reason is transcendent in this way. When we strive to discover something that we do not already know, or when we try to figure out if “what appears good to us” is “truly good,” we are moving beyond our current limitations, transcending current beliefs and desires. Hence, the “rule of reason” is also what allows us to become self-determining. When the rational part of the soul fails to unify a person in this way they become less a true whole, more a heap of warring appetites and passions. There is a “civil war in the soul.”32
This is why Socrates’s parting request to the Athenians after they have sentenced him to die in the Apology is that they should properly chastise and punish his sons if they do wrong. Socrates wants the Athenians to encourage his sons to live justly, so that they will not “think they are something when they are nothing.”33 To slip into vice—to be ruled over by mere parts of oneself—is to cease to function as a true whole, to become more a mere bundle of external causes, and so to slide towards non-being.
Relevant footnote: Indeed, Plato’s discussion of the “tyrannical man” in Book IX of the Republic sheds more light on why it is only reason that can unify and properly lead the soul. At 571b-c, Socrates distinguishes between necessary and unnecessary pleasures and desires. It is reason that is capable of making this distinction. When the lower parts of the soul “rule,” a person might prioritize the unnecessary over the necessary. Yet this can often lead to misery, since we will end up not having our more basic needs met because we have prioritized some ancillary concern. Consider here the wrathful individual who pursues vengeance at the expense of all else, and ends up miserable as a result.
Our wants are not unanalyzable primitives that the intellect must figure out how best to accommodate, but are in fact shaped by the intellect. — Count Timothy von Icarus
It seems obvious that there are empirical facts about what is good for us. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Aristotle didn't miss what Hume discovered - in fact it is not impossible that he derives his views in opposition to him (or his followers). That's a historical issue that I don't know enough to pronounce on.did Hume discover something seemingly obvious and fundamental that millennia of past thinkers simply missed? Or does Hume start from different assumptions? — Count Timothy von Icarus
I think this is a good question, but that it has an answer. Utility presents itself as something objective, but is just a posh way of talking about what people want. So it derives from sentiments.It seems to me that by citing different passages, one could show both that (1) Hume bases his ethics on sentiment, and (2) he bases his ethics on utility. the problem here of course may be confusion on my part. I would appreciate any attempt to clarify this issue. — Jedothek
Arguably, the "scientific" view of the world as value-neutral is a specialized stance, adopted in certain contexts, but abandoned completely when we return to ordinary lif
Surely, the will is not intellect. But when you refer to "rational wish", you are referring to a problem, not a conclusion. If all wishes were rational, it would not be possible to act irrationally. That's what the classic puzzle about the practical syllogism is about. Is the conclusion words/thoughts? They are not action. Is the conclusion action? That has no place in a syllogism. Hume doesn't need to deflate anything. Plato recognized this problem in the form of what he called "akrasia" and we call "weakness of will", articulated as "how is it possible to know what is the better action and yet execute the worse one?"Right, the will is not the intellect, that's what the passage gets at. However, Aristotle has motivating desire coming from appetite, spirit, and rational wish, from the rational soul/intellect. Hume has it coming only from the appetites and passions because the intellect/nous has been deflated to just ratio. — Count Timothy von Icarus
That's true. If you add a criterion for what is good or bad to theoretical reason, you can derive practical syllogisms. Only it only applies to some things. It's in the nature of rocks that there is no good or bad for them, only what happens. In addition, what is good for the plague bacillus is bad for human beings. Finally, I accept that there are some things that are good for human beings as such. But it doesn't follow that there are not other things that are good for some human beings, but not for others. That even applies to some foods. In addition, there are some foods that become poisons in excessive amounts. When you try to implement the generalization, you very quickly get into trouble.But perhaps more important is the idea that facts about what is good for beings, their telos, can be reasoned about from the nature of things, because the world isn't value free. "Food is good for man" or "water is good for plants" are accessible to theoretical reason as facts. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Well, I like to distinguish between science and scientism. It's a complicated issue. There has been much over-reaching since the original battles. But the original battle was, IMO, about the over-reaching of theologians in claiming that the Bible was the ultimate authority on physics.This is "scientific" only in the sense that proponents of this view tend to want to conflate it with "science" in order to give it legitimacy. And yet science cannot exist without distinctions of value, as between good evidence and bad evidence, good argument and bad argument, science and pseudoscience, good scientific habits and bad ones, etc. Notions that one ought not simply falsify one's data, or argue in bad faith for whatever is expedient is, or turn science into power politics, etc. are of course, value-laden. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Surely, the will is not intellect. But when you refer to "rational wish", you are referring to a problem, not a conclusion. If all wishes were rational, it would not be possible to act irrationally
That's what the classic puzzle about the practical syllogism is about. Is the conclusion words/thoughts? They are not action.
Plato, on the other hand, does supply a bridge in his third element, thumos. Thumos differs from appetite in that it is capable of submitting to reason (or better, nous is capable of training thumos. When that doesn't work out, reason is incapable of controlling both "thumos" and appetite. That's why I prefer the translation "emotion" for "thumos", since emotions include a cognitive element and so can be seen to bridge the gap.
Plato, on the other hand, does supply a bridge in his third element, thumos. Thumos differs from appetite in that it is capable of submitting to reason (or better, nous is capable of training thumos. When that doesn't work out, reason is incapable of controlling both "thumos" and appetite. That's why I prefer the translation "emotion" for "thumos", since emotions include a cognitive element and so can be seen to bridge the gap.
Finally, I accept that there are some things that are good for human beings as such. But it doesn't follow that there are not other things that are good for some human beings, but not for others. That even applies to some foods. In addition, there are some foods that become poisons in excessive amounts. When you try to implement the generalization, you very quickly get into trouble.
More seriously, that argument does enable one to work out what is good for some beings, at least. As it hapens, I'm content with that relativistic notion of good, but it may be that you are looking for something higher or deeper, such as "what is good?". I don't have any idea how to answer that question and doubt whether it has an answer. What's worse is that people often think they have an answer to that question when they do not, and that is the source of much evil. (I don't blame reason as such for that. I do blame the difficulty in being sure that one has not made a mistake.)
Ah! Well, that's a different kettle of fish. But then I'm not clear what we are talking about when we talk and "the will"! Why don't we just say that all three souls have the power to act.Rational wish relates to the rational soul, but there are also desires of the sensible and vegetative soul. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Thanks for this. I hesitated about this, because I was sure that he recognizes akrasia but couldn't come up with a reference. (I sometimes pursue these questions when writing replies, but they often lead down a rabbit-hole and distract me.)Plato, for his part, actually seems to deny the possibility of weakness of will in a number of places, the Parmenides being the place where he discusses this at most length. — Count Timothy von Icarus
It has always seemed odd to me that our conception of reason is so narrow. I've taken to using "reasonable" when talking about reason that doesn't fit the current definition.the intellect has been reduced to "the means by which one moves from premise to conclusion." In that case, Hume would be correct, reason can never motivate action. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Thanks for the reference. I thought there must be one, but it is a long time since I read De Anima. But then, why do we talk about "the will" as different from "the intellect"?Crucially, the will is also itself an intellectual power, part of the rational soul (Aristotle says "the will is in reason" (De Anima, III, 9), see also Aquinas Summa Theologiae, I, Q82. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Here's another problem. What on earth is supposed to be wrong with hunger and thirst? Surely it is entirely rational and choiceworthy to want to eat and drink, even though it is not choiceworthy to do either to excess or to consume inappropriate solids or liquids. The trouble is, IMO, that we look for something that is guaranteed to be right and call it reason. We ought to be consistent and say that our intellect, like our appetites and emotions, is sometimes right, and sometimes wrong.For Plato, the rational part of the soul has its own desires, which can motivate us to action. Indeed, it is reason's desire to know truth, and to know what is truly good, as opposed to what merely appears to be good (appetites) or is said to be good by others (spirited part), that drives his entire psychology. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Integration of the personality is certainly very desirable. But I'm not sure that the model of a charioteer is the only possibility. How about a partnership? That could achieve the same end.That's what the entire model of reflexive freedom and self-determination hinges on, the idea that we can shape our own appetites, that reason can (and ought be) the master of the passions and appetites. — Count Timothy von Icarus
I agree with that. Although, I would usually say that the mere desire to do something bad, is almost always bad, but not as bad as doing it.This is obviously very different from modern views where "no desire is bad, only acts," — Count Timothy von Icarus
I agree with that. One of many nails that A hits right on the head.We should not expect that ethics can be reduced to general maxims or any great deal of precision (Aristotle for his part warns against this at the outset of the Ethics). — Count Timothy von Icarus
I'm not necessarily aiming to save Hume. Understanding him would be sufficient.This doesn't save Hume though. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Why can't Hume be an anti-realist?However, if Hume is not to be an implicit anti-realist (or at least a skeptic) he is in the position of having to argue that we can know, as a fact, through reason, that "x is truly most choice-worthy," but must then turn around and claim that "x is most choice-worthy" does not ever imply "choose x," which is absurd. — Count Timothy von Icarus
True, very true. Both kinds of error are errors. I'm only recommending what Hume recommends - "judicious scepticism".My rejoinder would be that paralysis over fear of error can often be every bit as damaging as fear of error itself. There is what Hegel termed in the preface to the Phenomenology, "the fear of error become fear of truth." — Count Timothy von Icarus
I have little idea what Yeats had in mind and suspect that I wouldn't approve of it. Nonethless this, sadly, seems to be a suitable motto for our times.The best lack all conviction, while the worst
Are full of passionate intensity. — Yeats - The Second Coming
Hume understands taste to be wider than that. For him, “taste in morals, eloquence, or beauty” assigns either “approbation” or “disapprobation” (or some combination of both) to objects of taste. — Ludwig V
It seemed rather odd to me, at first. Then, I realizes that I should have seen it all along. It's one of those switches in perception that happen from time to time. It seems very odd at first, but then one realizes that the writing off of taste as just arbitrary choices is completely inadequate.That's how I understand taste, too. — Moliere
We are so used to thinking of reason as about truth, by definition, that it takes a jolt to realize that there could be varieties - domains that should be included in it. There's more to life than truth.That is, even if there are moral truths, it seems most human beings -- if they operate according to any kind of reasoned path at all -- operate in accord with a sort of aesthetics of morality. — Moliere
Yes. My asking why philosophers are so dismissive of appetites left out the passions. The same question applies. Neither appetites nor passions are optional extras.Passion isn't some nullification of morality or reason, but simply the answer to how human nature does it. — Moliere
That's fair enough. It seems to me another application of his approach to philosophy. Faced with scepticism, he simply refuses to argue, but points out that we will not really accept the conclusion. We will carry on believing in causation and so much the worse for the sceptics' reason. Here, he transforms the subjectivism that the new science imposes on morality and aesthetics into an account of how we do it. To adapt W, "this is what we do".And it can be taken in either realist(naturalist) or anti-realist(phenomenology-as-ontology) ways -- I don't think he was clear on that because that's kind of an our-time question. He's dealing with an entirely different set of problems. — Moliere
Yes, it would be interesting to know why nobody liked it. People still seem to prefer the Enqiry but I'm not clear why.And, arguably, an entirely different set of problems from his time, since his Treatise was not well received in his time. — Moliere
Yes. I don't think it is all that strange that they are close. One's philosophical enemies should, arguably, be kept even closer then one's friends. I believe that he cites Berkeley as well.Though the influence on Kant I think cements him as an important figure (and on that I tend to think of Kant and Hume as closer than often depicted) — Moliere
It seemed rather odd to me, at first. Then, I realizes that I should have seen it all along. It's one of those switches in perception that happen from time to time. It seems very odd at first, but then one realizes that the writing off of taste as just arbitrary choices is completely inadequate. — Ludwig V
We are so used to thinking of reason as about truth, by definition, that it takes a jolt to realize that there could be varieties - domains that should be included in it. There's more to life than truth. — Ludwig V
Truth, Goodness and Beauty would be usual list. One might expand it in various ways. But, because I was introduced to philosophy via Socrates, I've always thought that the activity is really the thing. Study is all very well, of course. But it is a mostly a solitary occupation. Dialogue (with others) is not merely desirable, but of the essence.Philosophy is more than the study of the predicate "...is true", to put it into OLP terms. — Moliere
There is one problem here that I can't get past. Hume's account is right to say that it is not the case that everybody's opinion is of equal value (although everybody is entitled to an opinion) but his account of the standard of taste seems elitist (and I suspect was intended to be elitist in its application). I can't let that go. So my application of this account allows that anyone may acquire the qualfications simply from being interested and opinionated and talking to other interested and opinionated people about what they see and hear.He requires it to give rules for "confirming one sentiment and condemning another." But it must also explain why some sentiments are better and some are worse (NOT true or false). He gives five criteria for identifying people who are capable of doing this - “Strong sense, united to delicate sentiment, improved by practice, perfected by comparison, and cleared of all prejudice ..." So the standard of taste is the consensus of those who are qualified to pass judgement. But such people are rare, and consensus over time is crucial to avoid mistakes. — Ludwig V
There is one problem here that I can't get past. Hume's account is right to say that it is not the case that everybody's opinion is of equal value (although everybody is entitled to an opinion) but his account of the standard of taste seems elitist (and I suspect was intended to be elitist in its application). I can't let that go. So my application of this account allows that anyone may acquire the qualfications simply from being interested and opinionated and talking to other interested and opinionated people about what they see and hear. — Ludwig V
I wondered if it was because he was a noble that these were his prejudices -- but reading the wikipedia page on his life it looks like he's more of an elitist because he was just that smart: — Moliere
The moment one touches a transcendental, one touches being itself, a likeness of God, an absolute, that which ennobles and delights our life; one enters into the domain of the spirit. It is remarkable that men really communicate with one another only by passing through being or one of its properties. Only in this way do they escape from the individuality in which matter encloses them. If they remain in the world of their sense needs and of their sentimental egos, in vain do they tell their stories to one another, they do not understand each other. They observe each other without seeing each other, each one of them infinitely alone, even though work or sense pleasures bind them together. But let one touch the good and Love, like the saints, the true, like an Aristotle, the beautiful, like a Dante or a Bach or a Giotto, then contact is made, souls communicate. Men are really united only by the spirit; light alone brings them together, intellectualia et rationalia omnia congregans, et indestructibilia faciens. 74
Art in general tends to make a work. But certain arts tend to make a beautiful work, and in this they differ essentially from all the others. The work to which all the other arts tend is itself ordered to the service of man, and is therefore a simple means; and it is entirely enclosed in a determined material genus. The work to which the fine arts tend is ordered to beauty; as beautiful, it is an end, an absolute, it suffices of itself; and if as work-to-be-made, it is material and enclosed in a genus, as beautiful it belongs to the kingdom of the spirit and plunges deep into the transcendence and the infinity of being.
That's not particularly shocking. Why would it be? I'm well aware that there are people who think that.Would it shock you to learn that I find Hume's aesthetics to be horrifically deflationary as well? :rofl: — Count Timothy von Icarus
Of course how people think of, and approach, the art they create affects what they create. What's noteworthy is that they all seem to manage to produce beautiful works of art. Which makes one wonder how relevant those theories are. But of course they are, because they set the criteria by which we can appreciate their beauty. We have to learn that; it doesn't just appear automatically.I really do think dominant theories of aesthetics affect art too. The Romantic period is full of great art. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Liking sounds remarkably like something Hume would approce of. Are you in pursuit of Beauty? or Truth? Here's my problem. How do you know you have found those good things, and are they Good? I find myself so much in awe of their transcendent magnificence that I feel it would be arrogant to think that I have. I've seen the disastrous cruelties that people who think that they know what they are can commit to feel that my attitude is more reasonable.There is much to like too in the more cosmic view of Beauty found in the likes of Saint Maximus the Confessor, or in the Romantics, in Schelling, Goethe, Schiller, etc., or in Morrison or Kundera in more recent times. — Count Timothy von Icarus
It is remarkable that men really communicate with one another only by passing through being or one of its properties. Only in this way do they escape from the individuality in which matter encloses them. If they remain in the world of their sense needs and of their sentimental egos, in vain do they tell their stories to one another, they do not understand each other.
It is only the philosopher who doesn't see this as a form of understanding, among all the various other ways people do, in fact, really communicate with one another without passing through being or one of its properties. — Moliere
This reads as a version of what the monastics are trying to claim when they say their way of life is better than the dancer's. In one way, it's only natural to feel that one's own way of life is better than any other and it may well be better for those who pursue it. But I don't think it is therefore necessarily better for everyone, nor that there is no possibility of communication between those who pursue different ways of life. We're all human beings, after all. Surely that is sufficient ground for at least recognizing each other.Men are really united only by the spirit; light alone brings them together, intellectualia et rationalia omnia congregans, et indestructibilia faciens.
This seems to me to describe a way of thinking as a phenomenon without committing to a whole philosophical framework.Whenever I am occupied with even the tiniest logistical problem, e.g. trying to find the shortest axiom of the implicational calculus, I have the impression that I am confronted with a mighty construction of indescribably complexity and immeasureable rigidity. This construction has the effect on me of a concrete tangible object, fashioned from the hardest of materials, a hundred times stronger than concrete or steel. I cannot change anything in it; by intense labour, I merely find in it ever new details, and attain unshakable and eternal truths. Where and what is this ideal construction? A Catholic philosopher would say: it is in God, it is God’s thought. — J. Lukasiewicz, quoted in 'A Wittgenstein Workbook'
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.