↪Antony Nickles
But Witt shows is that the world has endless ways of being “rational” (having ways to account, though different), and so we can disagree intelligibly in relation from those practices. Ultimately we may not come to resolution, but that does not lead to the categorical failure of rationality, because a dispute also only happens at a time, in a context (which also gives our differences traction).
I don't think Wittgenstein shows this at all, as evidenced by the extremely diverse directions this thread is taken in by different Wittgensteinians. He leaves this incredibly vague; vague enough that a common take is that rationality just bottoms out in cultural presuppositions that cannot be analyzed. This view in turn makes any conflict between "heterogenous cultures" or "heterogenous language games," either purely affective/emotional or else simply a power struggle— i.e. "fight it out." This is especially true if the individual subject is just a nexus of signifiers and power discourses — Count Timothy von Icarus
92. However, we can ask: May someone have telling grounds for believing that the earth has only existed for a short time, say since his own birth? - Suppose he had always been told that, - would he have any good reason to doubt it? Men have believed that they could make the rain; why should not a king be brought up in the belief that the world began with him? And if Moore and this king were to meet and discuss, could Moore really prove his belief to be the right one? I do not say that Moore could not convert the king to his view, but it would be a conversion of a special kind; the king would be brought to look at the world in a different way. Remember that one is sometimes convinced of the correctness of a view by its simplicity or symmetry, i.e., these are what induce one to go over to this point of view. One then simply says something like: "That's how it must be”. (On Certainty)
Can I make a rule for myself, privately? Here "privately" means "not subject to enforcement by anything else (human or otherwise)". In other words, is it possible for the correct application of my rule to be solely determined by my application of it? In yet other words, if I make my rule and determine what is the correct application of it, is it meaningful to say that I am bound by it? — Ludwig V
In An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding and A Treatise of Human Nature, Hume proposed that the origin of our knowledge of necessary connections arises out of observation of the constant conjunction of certain impressions across many instances, so that causation is merely constant conjunction—after observing the constant conjunction between two events A and B for a duration of time, we become convinced that A causes B. However, this position raises problems, as it seems that certain kinds of constant conjunction are merely accidental and cannot be equated with causation.
An individual sees the sun rise in the east on 100 consecutive days. They become aware of the rule that the sun rises in the east, and then live by the rule that the sun rises in the east. — RussellA
Yes. I believe that this issue has been much discussed in relation to Wittgenstein, though I believe it is normally framed as the difference between a regularity and a rule. There is room for some argument about exactly what Hume said or believed, but I think it would be a distraction to pursue that here.However, as Hume pointed out, perceived constant conjunction of events in the world may be as much accidental as a rule. — RussellA
Even if within the community that B lives in there are public rules, B will only know about them from what she perceives through her senses. But as before, what she perceives through her senses to be a rule may in fact be accidental, meaning that if she does live her life following a rule, she must have made it herself. IE, B also lives by private rules. — RussellA
You are right to point out that each individual in a community needs to learn the rules for themselves It follows, therefore, that each of us must formulate the rules on the basis of our experience and apply them for themselves. What you seem to neglect is the point that our formulation and application of the rules is corrected by further experience. (Hume doesn't say that, but it is implicit in Hume's argument. Moreover, it is how we can distinguish between mere regularities and rules.)IE, if individuals live by rules, as Hume's principle of constant conjunction shows, the individual cannot have discovered them through their senses, but must have made them, and in this sense are private rules. If an individual has made the rule, then they must know how to correctly apply it. However, even if the individual has made the rule, they may or may not decide to be bound by it. — RussellA
An individual sees the sun rise in the east on 100 consecutive days. They become aware of the rule that the sun rises in the east, and then live by the rule that the sun rises in the east. — RussellA
I guess you mean when she makes a "leap" from the limited sample to a generalization and then treats that generalization as a rule, she has made the rule for herself. I also guess that the rule takes the form of "when the clock shows that it is morning, you can expect the sun to rise."But as before, what she perceives through her senses to be a rule may in fact be accidental, meaning that if she does live her life following a rule, she must have made it herself. — RussellA
Well, let's suppose that's correct. Then, in this case, what she knows is that she does not determine what is correct or incorrect. The sun does. That is, if the sun doesn't rise, she will need to abandon or modify the rule.If an individual has made the rule, then they must know how to correctly apply it. — RussellA
Yes. Hume's version of this seems to me to be that it is a brute fact of human nature that we build up expectations as a result of constant conjunctions. I'm not sure how far Wittgenstein would disagree.There is quite a lot of stage setting that would occur to understand if such an individual had such a rule. — Richard B
Hume is very clear that the we will not abandon our process of formulating generalizations from individual cases, no matter how persuasive the sceptic's arguments. Indeed, he recommends a month in the country as the appropriate cure for radical scepticism. The more I think about it, the less I understand why he has the reputation of being a sceptical philosopher - though he does recommend what he calls "judicious" scepticism; he's probably right about that.Once I have exhausted the justifications, I have reached bedrock, and my spade is turned. Then I am inclined to say: “This is simply what I do". — Phil. Inv. 217
If we say that rationality is a question of our agreement in ways of life, we seem to eliminate the distinction between those agreements that we call "correct" or "incorrect" by some standard that is not set by our agreement and those agreements that are simply a matter of making a deal, so that "correct" and "incorrect" do not apply. — Ludwig V
You will understand, I suppose, that I think that agreements that are correct or incorrect are, by and large, rational agreements and the other kind are, roughly, matters of taste or convenience or pragmatics. (The difficulty of agreements about values sits awkwardly between the two.) — Ludwig V
does [saying disagreements happen at a time and place] mean that such failures can eventually be overcome at other times and in other contexts? If so, then limitation doesn't seem to lie in reason itself, but in people's finite use of it, their patience, etc. — Count Timothy von Icarus
If the lion comment is taken head on it is just stupid. — Count Timothy von Icarus
There is quite a lot of stage setting that would occur to understand if such an individual had such a rule. — Richard B
I don't disagree with you. I would go further. There is a difference between agree what the criteria are to be, e.g. on what the defining example on 1 foot is to be; that is not a question of truth and falsity or correct and incorrect. (How they decide to change the standard metre in Paris is way beyond me.) Agreeing that this path is 3 feet wide is different, and true/false and correct/incorrect do apply.“Agreement” is here not the same either. We come to an agreement on some criteria—like how long one foot will be—but we do not agree “to” our practices (it is “agree” in the sense more of aligning, over our entire history of doing things). Still, we do judge whether, say, an apology, is correct or incorrect, but the criteria for that are different than true and false, as I can accept an apology that you do poorly (“accepting” is part of how it works differently, its “rationality” or “grammar” as Witt calls it). — Antony Nickles
I certainly wasn't intending to endorse moral scepticism. I'm sorry I wasn't more explicit. However, it is true that, if we regard moral debate as a practice, we have to recognize both that facts play a part in those debates and that it is not possible to deduce any moral proposition from factual propositions alone. Hence I said that moral statements "sit awkwardly" between those two (admittedly very simple-minded) categories.It is exactly this framework that interprets skepticism as a theoretical “problem”, rather than the discovery that there is no fact that will ensure resolution of our moral conflicts, thus we are responsible for solving our ongoing disagreements, because we do have the means. — Antony Nickles
I have no problem whatever with this. I would add that the wish to step outside any particular practice, however, is incoherent. Any attempt to do simply generates a new context.All criteria reflect our interests in our lives (what and how we value something), it’s only metaphysical criteria that wish to step outside of any particular practice or situation. — Antony Nickles
I have looked at your big discussion. It needs a bit of time. For the moment, I'm really quite confused here.Sorry, it is not that we cannot understand lions, just not talking ones; it is meant to be the statement of a fact, not a scientific claim (which I try to explain here), because it is said in contrast to when we CAN work out other cultural practices, to show that we sometimes just choose not to. — Antony Nickles
agreement is different from agreeing with someone else where we shall go for lunch — Ludwig V
I'm not sure that all moral disagreements can be resolved — Ludwig V
I would add that the wish to step outside any particular practice, however, is incoherent. Any attempt to do simply generates a new context. — Ludwig V
2. Are you suggesting that we could work out the common ground with a lion, but that we choose not to? Which suggests that we could if we wanted to. — Ludwig V
Are you saying that we can understand lions, but that if a lion could speak to us, we would not be able to understand what was said? Of course, communication would not be instant, but Wittgenstein seems to be suggesting that there is some insoluble problem. I can't see why he would think so. — Ludwig V
Your example of apology is a very interesting one, that I would love to discuss separately; it is very relevant to ethics. — Ludwig V
Well, yes. I was thinking that the same is true for mathematics; but mathematics is set up to exist in that "context". The "metaphysics" that I've seen tries to do the same with ideas that are not designed in the same way. Fish out of water. Mathematics as a whale or a dolphin. Or Wittgenstein'sBut the metaphysical problem is generalized and abstracted out of time, place, actors, i.e. anything we would call “a context”. — Antony Nickles
We have got on to slippery ice where there is no friction, and so, in a certain sense, the conditions are ideal; but also, just because of that, we are unable to walk. We want to walk: so we need friction. Back to the rough ground! — PI 107
"Consent" would do. Perhaps we need a specialized term for these situations. The thing is, in these radical situations, we are learning skills. That's not a context in which you can give "informed consent" and once you've learnt the skill, it's too late to ask questions. I didn't ask to learn English and wondering whether English is correct or adequate or whatever is meaningless - because I can only do it in English (and, possibly one or two other languages).Yes, a “form of life” is not a conclusion or argued, etc (though “acquiesce” implies choice; we are indoctrinated, assimilated—Rousseau’s “consent” unconsciously.) That is not to say we don’t have forms of argument or refutation, means of judging loyalty and fairness (“you picked last time”). — Antony Nickles
That's true. But I think there's another sense in which frailty is systemic. I'm referring to Nussbaum's Fragility of Goodness. But we don't need to discuss that here.But the point is that that frailty is only a possible occurrence, and so should not be interpreted into a systemic problem (concluding that there is no “rationality”, intelligibility). — Antony Nickles
OK. I think I get that. I have been known to throw off an example only to find later that it completely back-fires.He wanted something that would be an uncontroversial “very general fact of nature” (PI #143 and p. 230) that he presumes would be accepted as a fact, such as: parrots don’t talk to themselves (#344). — Antony Nickles
There are such dilemmas. But there are also dilemmas where the problem is precisely that everyone "knows" what to do, but can't agree with each other, because they insist on framing the problem differently. I'm afraid abortion, in my book, is one such case.And Witt’s idea of a moral dilemma is not like a clash of interests about a certain type of topic (say about abortion), but when everyone is at a loss as to what to do, how to go on—which is an event (and could involve any of our practices). — Antony Nickles
"Even Homer nods" and the temptation is very hard to resist, sometimes.I would say he choose poorly (though perhaps, as worse with Nietzsche, he can’t help poking people in the eye). — Antony Nickles
I'm not sure "arrogant" quite captures it. I prefer to think that the modesty he expresses in the Preface to PI is sincere. But it can come over as arrogant. But, by the same token, I do find other philosophers to be arrogant, though perhaps not quite in the same way. It's the idea that you can (should) present examples and observations and leave the reader to work out their significance. That may be over-confident, but it's not stupid. (I read somewhere that the practice of his parents when he was a child, when he needed telling off, was to leave appropriate books by his bedside. If true, that would explain it.)This is Witt’s arrogant style on full display, as he will even state without argument the implications he posits for, say, “believing”, as if everyone would agree. — Antony Nickles
Yes, and much more interesting that trudging round and round the same few dogmas. I've just re-read, after several decades, Anscombe's "Intention", which is similar. But then, real ethics is not about quasi-legal rules, but, arguably, about forms of life.J.L. Austin’s A Plea for Excuses is a work about ethics in that way. — Antony Nickles
once you've learnt the skill, it's too late to ask questions — Ludwig V
It's the idea that you can (should) present examples and observations and leave the reader to work out their significance — Ludwig V
A similar thing that crops up in these relativistic accounts is a sort of cognitive relativism. I'll let A.C. Grayling describe this one:
Cognitive relativism is a troubling thesis. Consider the point that it makes the concepts of truth, reality, and value a matter of what sharers in a form of life happen to make of them at a particular time and place, with other forms of life at other times and places giving rise to different, perhaps utterly different or even contrary, conceptions of them. In effect this means that the concepts in question are not concepts of truth and the rest, as we usually wish to understand them, but concepts of opinion and belief. We are, if cognitive relativism is true (but what does true now mean?), in error if we think that truth and knowledge have the meanings we standardly attach to them, for there is only relative truth, there is only reality as we, in this conceptual community at this period in its history, conceive it. — Count Timothy von Icarus
I think so. Perhaps a read-through of that might be worth while - but let's do the Blue Book first.I am going to start a read-though of The Blue Book soon, but the Anscombe sounds interesting. — Antony Nickles
Yes. Existing practices and forms of life are a starting-point, and one cannot start without one. There's a paradox, then, that our existing practices are a basis for questioning practices. But a paradoxical conclusion is just "contrary to or surprising" our existing beliefs and expectations - that's not necessarily a problem.Also, because we have a practice is why and how it can be rational to question, push back, live differently, etc. — Antony Nickles
Good point. It perhaps justifies the practice of letting the readers draw their own conclusions. Risky, though.As well, the part people skip over is that his examples (rule-following, pointing, “seeing”, etc.) are practices that everyone can weigh in on (we each have an equal right to claims/there is no privileged position), so the proposed criteria we use, and the “grammar” of how they work, have to be accepted (by you) for it to be philosophical worth drawing conclusions from (as evidence). — Antony Nickles
Quite so. But perhaps it is a bit of a bogeyman. After all the trouble that goes with absolutism might be even greater. The key problem there is establishing that one has actually got hold of the absolute truth. All too often, one has not. It would be better if people were much more cautious and sceptical of such temptations.I guess there is a lot of "trouble" to go around when it comes to this thesis. — Richard B
Oh, surely, members of the same family can disagree without ceasing to be members of the family. There's no black-and-white rule here - just shades of grey.I should say that I feel more inclined to just say that their concept of "truth" no longer resembles mine; so sooner or later they are not part of the family but mere strangers. — Richard B
Do we need to police the use of the words "truth", "reality" and "value", so we can ensure a unifying meaning for each of these terms?
Oh, surely, members of the same family can disagree without ceasing to be members of the family. There's no black-and-white rule here - just shades of grey.
Yes, metaphors (and analogies) have to be interpreted and are all too easily misinterpreted. When it comes to family relations, for example. There are also what are sometimes called mixed families, in which the "normal" biological relations do not hold. There is an awkward question about adopted and step- children, isn't there. Is the biological or social relationship the "real" parent? Opinions differ. Which illustrates my point.Well, herein lies the difficulty of relying too heavily on metaphors. When it comes to family relations, it seems that they can exist even if no one believes they do. For example, if Ajax is the biological father of Ophelia, this relation of paternity exists even if neither Ajax nor Ophelia (nor any of their family members) are aware of it. And not only that, but evidence of the paternity relationship is "out there" to be discovered. — Count Timothy von Icarus
My comment was in relation to this. But I took it, in context, to be about our social relationships - forms of life, practices, etc. So my comment was intended to refer to the social family, rather than the biological one.I should say that I feel more inclined to just say that their concept of "truth" no longer resembles mine; so sooner or later they are not part of the family but mere strangers. — Richard B
But perhaps you knew that and were pointing out the alternative conception of the family and applying the point to suggest that the True and the Good might exist "out there" whatever our relationship or non-relationship with it happens to be - and why not add Beauty to the list?Yet because this holds for families does it mean it holds for notions o f the True or the Good? — Count Timothy von Icarus
'm not sure how the vague metaphor here is supposed to address the point TBH.
But funny enough this is a point of contention in Wittgensteinian circles precisely because he uses a lot of vague metaphors. — Count Timothy von Icarus
As I see it, A.C Graying desire is to hold on to the idea that there is one common essence for "truth", "reality", and "value" because the only alternative is "cognitive relativism." However, what I was suggesting is we need not fall into relativism either. First, words like "truth", "reality", and "value" will have multiple uses and thus have family resemblances that will related these word conceptually. These multiple uses are discovered by examining the forms of life which are grounded in the some human activity. That said, these concepts can take place in such radically different forms of life, the family resemblances are not strong enough to call them related. Hence, I introduce the term "stranger" to describe such a case. For example, if we visit another world where the inhabitants utilize symbols like 1, 2, +, -, etc and made expressions such as 1 + 1 = 3 were carried out, would we want to say this is some sort of arithmetic that was carried out? Or is the judgment so radically different that we would not want to call it "arithmetic"? To say "truth" is relative seems to presuppose that there is something conceptual linking all these words together but somehow the outcomes conflict. But that need not be the case, if these concepts are used is such dramatically different ways in which humans act and judge in entirely different ways, why should we even talk as if they had some relationship that deserve to fall under the banner of "truth".
I'm sorry. I was careless. I'm would not dream of contesting the point that the way we reproduce, biologically and culturally (because reproduction happens at both levels) is bound to be important in any human form of life and any human practices.There are different family structures, there are half siblings, step siblings, etc. Yet, what culture believes in people who do not have biological mothers or fathers? Outside of miracles or myth, where do people accept: "that person was never in the womb?" or "oh yes, Jessie over there is another immaculate conception?" — Count Timothy von Icarus
Yes. Huxley imagines the culmination in "Brave New World". It's hard not to think that being born from a jar and raised in a baby factory would have a profound influence on subsequent culture. Huxley doesn't follow through on that. Also, as it happens, the animals that we feel closest to reproduce much as we do.Absolutely nowhere is the answer. It is truly miraculous for there to be a human being without a biological father or biological mother. A cloned human being would still have a "parent" who had two biological parents and they would still (barring astounding scientific progress) need to be born. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Yes. Christianity seems to have latched on to the sales technique that rests on making a big attention-getting claim, even it is wildly improbable and most likely false, or, charitably, metaphorical.If someone told you they had no father and had never been born of a woman would your reaction be a shrug and the thought: "why yes, people of some cultures aren't born, I suppose they spring forth from rocks fully formed? There is no truth about biological parentage in these parts." You have to be on a severe overdose of pomo to believe it. — Count Timothy von Icarus
There are people around who think that is the choice. But I misjudged you it seems. "False dichotomy" must be the answer. I'm not sure I could prove it to a determined sceptic. But empirically, our language supports both doctrines, so it must be horses for courses - in other words, a matter decided for each practice. Is that the way you would go?And to be honest, I think the continual contrasting of pernicious forms of relativism with "Final Answers" (capitalized of course), "One True Canonical Descriptions," "The Only Right Way," and the like, is a strawman/false dichotomy. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Would it not be a pragmatic decision? Not that I could articulate what the criteria might be for making such a decision - whether to see all the practices linked or "truth" as multiply ambiguous. One might also go back to consider what motivates absolutism/relativism. It's a question that Cavell might ask.if these concepts are used is such dramatically different ways in which humans act and judge in entirely different ways, why should we even talk as if they had some relationship that deserve to fall under the banner of "truth". — Richard B
But to my mind this capability doesn't jive well with the concept of entirely disparate, sui generis forms of reason (e.g., that Chinese reason is entirely different from French reason). — Count Timothy von Icarus
But has not history shown that what intelligent people called “reasonable” and “unreasonable” has changed from time to time
And yet this thesis seems entirely implausible. For instance, I have never heard of a culture who does arithmetic completely different from any other culture. Where is the arithmetic that is untranslatable? — Count Timothy von Icarus
And aside from that, it seems to leave the door open on an all encompassing skepticism, for on this account how can anyone be sure that they truly share a form of life with anyone else? — Count Timothy von Icarus
I'm not at all sure the biological is what W meant by "forms of life". It is, indeed, something that all human beings share. However, some people talk of "a common humanity", which is also hard to interpret, but seems to be related more to the possibility of what we might call a personal relationship. But we are also quite ready to classify some human beings as inhuman or subhuman or animal - mainly on moral grounds, but sometimes in reference to the breakdown of social structures.I think these sorts of biological constants (constant across diverse historical/cultural variances) is what Wittgenstein is sometimes pointing to with the "form of life." — Count Timothy von Icarus
So we have three levels - at least - of forms of life. Biological, cultural, cognitive. How many more? In any case, all these are intertwined and inseparable in practice. I mean that what we actually have to deal with is the combination of all the levels in action.But this is cultural relativism, not cognitive relativism. — Count Timothy von Icarus
It would indeed. But we would face the problem of detecting life before we could progress to detecting conscious "rational" life. No doubt we would be "limited" by comparisons with what we acknowledge as life on this planet. But a form of life that can thrive on Venus would, surely have to be rather different from the forms of life that thrive on Earth. No matter, the comparison with Earth is a starting-point and that's all we really need.We would share with extraterrestrials all that is common to all corners of the universe, limits on the information carrying capacity of various media, ratios, etc. And this might profitably be thought of as an even broader "form of life," the form of life common to all organisms living in our universe. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Your discussion is really very ambitious. If we consider all the possible problems at once, they will be overwhelming. We need to deal with each problem as it comes up, with the tools (intellectual and technological) we have at hand. If you had asked Aristotle to build a nuclear collider, it would have been an overwhelming, impossible problem. Now look at us!On this view, if one reads Aristotle's Organon, it might seem that Aristotle is discussing a logic quite similar to our own (and to "common sense") but really there is no way for us to know if we mean the same thing. Being separated by vast cultural differences, it rather seems we should not mean the same things when we refer to syllogisms, premises, etc. — Count Timothy von Icarus
The underlined phrases are the give-away that something is being smuggled in to the argument. Those nebulous doubts are the essence of scepticism. But the desire for perfection is the enemy of progress. So it is best to do what we can and progress as we can, without being put off by the destuctive fears and ambitions of the sceptic.Now the cognitive relativist can always claims that different forms of arithmetic and logic only seem translatable—that we don't really understand Aristotle or Shankara at all. However, this seems pretty far fetched. And aside from that, it seems to leave the door open on an all encompassing skepticism, for on this account how can anyone be sure that they truly share a form of life with anyone else? — Count Timothy von Icarus
Underdetermination is another bogey-man. If we have a rule that works, we use until it doesn't - then we come up with another one. We can't possibly deal with all the possibilities at once, so we deal with what we have to hand.Wittgenstein's point that any set of actions is still consistent with an infinite number of rules still holds. This holds with the study of nature as well. Any sort of "natural law," based solely on past observations seems doomed to underdetermination. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Of course it has, and that's a good thing. On this planet, the common tradition gives a reasonable basis for making reasonable translations from one epoch to another.But has not history shown that what intelligent people called “reasonable” and “unreasonable” has changed from time to time. — Richard B
The supposition is not really specific enough to sensibly answer the question. We have to make decisions step by step, acknowledging mis-steps as we discover themYep, and this was my point, if they are completely different in action/ judgement, why call it arithmetic at all. — Richard B
That I can agree with.Well it will not be from some self evident absolute certain proposition. But that we act and judge similarly in most case to sustain the form of life. — Richard B
One need not take as one's target so radical a form of the thesis to show that cognitive relativism is unacceptable, however. This can be demonstrated as follows. Suppose that cognitive relativism is the case. How then do we recognize another form of life as another form of life? The ability to detect that something is a form of life and that it differs from our own surely demands that there be a means for us to identify its presence and to specify what distinguishes it from ours. But such means are unavailable if the other form of life is impenetrable to us, that is, if it is closed against our attempts to interpret it enough to say that it is a form of life. This means that if we are to talk of other forms of life at all we must be able to recognize them as such; we must be able to recognize the existence of behaviour and patterns of practices which go to make up a form of life in which there is agreement among the participants by reference to which their practices can go on. Moreover, if we are to see that the form of life is different from our own we have to be able to recognize the differences; this is possible only if we can interpret enough of the other form of life to make those differences apparent. And therefore there has to be sufficient common ground between the two forms of life to permit such interpretation.
The supposition is not really specific enough to sensibly answer the question. We have to make decisions step by step, acknowledging mis-steps as we discover them — Ludwig V
Certainly, I would agree with that. Further investigation required. On the other hand, I wouldn't dream of calling them insane. This practice is incomprehensible but there's no need - yet - to dismiss it as insanity. After all, there's a preliminary investigation needed to work out whether insanity is a concept that can be applied to them at all.In short this money, or what looks like money, has among them a quite different role from among us. — Wittgenstein RFM
This is where this issue began. I think what I was trying to say that a concept of arithmetic that was incommensurable with our arithmetic seems to me incoherent. I can imagine a practice that appears to be like arithmetic, but isn't. But I can't imagine a practice of arithmetic that couldn't be translated into our arithmetic. The possibility of translation is a criterion for classifying a practice as arithmetic. I suppose we might find, as it were, fragments of arithmetic in various practices, but not a coherent single system. Or there might be parts of our arithmetic discernible in their practice and other parts missing.And yet this thesis seems entirely implausible. For instance, I have never heard of a culture who does arithmetic completely different from any other culture. Where is the arithmetic that is untranslatable? — Count Timothy von Icarus
Yes. But that would exclude the possibility of the kinds of interaction that would allow us to say that these people are people, or possibly even that they are alive.However, it is not impossible for the observing community who can see these differences to carry on conversation among themselves since there is agreement in use and judgment in their language. — Richard B
Re PI 65, I think this has simply been proven wrong by advances in linguistics and information theory. We can identify similarities. I find it hard to even imagine Wittgenstein wanting to argue this point in the modern context given his respect for the sciences. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Re PI 65, I think this has simply been proven wrong by advances in linguistics and information theory. We can identify similarities. I find it hard to even imagine Wittgenstein wanting to argue this point in the modern context given his respect for the sciences. — Count Timothy von Icarus
But Wittgenstein doesn't argue that we can't identify similarities. He just argues that we do not need to identify a single similarity as the basis for every characteristic.Re PI 65, I think this has simply been proven wrong by advances in linguistics and information theory. We can identify similarities. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Similarities are the elements of family resemblances.And the upshot of these considerations is: we see a complicated net-work of similarities overlapping and criss-crossing: similarities in the large and in the small — Phil. Inv. 66
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.