P3: To value something entails it is not an end in itself. — Bob Ross
The formula is thus: one should never treat a person as solely a means towards an end, but always (at least) simultaneously an end in themselves—i.e., FET. — Bob Ross
This is a vacuous definition, not an ostensible claim.P1: If something is solely a means towards an end, then it is not an end in itself. — Bob Ross
Demonstrate this entailment.P2: To value something entails it is solely a means towards an end.
Invalid inference from underdetermined "propositions". Ergo, "FET proof" (C6) fails.C1: To value something entails it is not an end in itself.
I ground the entire (normative and applied) ethical theory in one moral judgment: “one ought to be rational”. — Bob Ross
There is no moral fact which dictates that one ought to be rational, but any sane person will agree to this moral judgment (subjectively) — Bob Ross
t is important to explicate what exactly is meant by ‘rationality’. By this term I mean ‘the quality of being based in reason and logic’. — Bob Ross
P1: If something is solely a means towards an end, then it is not an end in itself.
P2: To value something entails it is solely a means towards an end.
C1: To value something entails it is not an end in itself. — Bob Ross
P3: To value something entails it is not an end in itself.
P4: Minds are something.
C2: To value a mind entails that they are not an end in themselves. — Bob Ross
P5: Persons (i.e., beings with personhood) are ends in themselves.
P6: Minds are persons.
C3: Minds are ends in themselves. — Bob Ross
P6: One should not accept contradictions as true.
P7: If one values a mind, then they are contradicting themselves (because it concedes that a mind is and is not an end in itself). [ !(C2 ^ C3) ]
C4: One should not value minds. — Bob Ross
P7: One should not value minds.
P8: To consider a mind valueless is to value them at 0.
C5: One should not consider minds valueless. — Bob Ross
P9: If one should not value a mind (including a value of 0), then minds should be considered invaluable.
P10: One should not value a mind (including a value of 0).
C6: Minds should be considered invaluable. — Bob Ross
From the sheer impossibility (without conceding a contradiction) to value something which creates value, any rational agent is required treat creators of value (i.e., minds: persons) always as simultaneously ends in themselves: as invaluable. It follows from this the sanctity of persons (i.e., of minds) because they are invaluable — Bob Ross
P1: If something is solely a means towards an end, then it is not an end in itself.
P2: Persons are ends in themselves.
P3: One should abide by the law of non-contradiction.
P4: To treat a person as solely a means towards an end is to contradict their nature (i.e., to contradict P2).
C: One should not treat a person as solely a means towards an end, but always as (at least) simultaneously an end in themselves.
P1 merely highlights that if something is just a means towards some end (and just a means) then it cannot be an end itself—e.g., if mowing my lawn is a means towards making my house look presentable (and that being the only consideration), then mowing my lawn is solely means to an end and that end is making my house look presentable. P2 notes that persons (i.e., minds) are ends in themselves: persons are the only type of existence in reality which is capable of having ends and of being ultimately the final end for itself—e.g., although making my house look good may have been the end within the previous example’s context, it is likewise only a means toward another end (like making myself look respectable to my guests) but it will, without any consideration of other people as ends, ultimately bottom out at the final end of myself: I ultimately mow my lawn, in the case that I am not considering other people as ends, for myself—for my benefit. Persons are the only creators capable of setting out hypothetical imperatives (i.e., contextual ends) for the sake of themselves (as the final end) and are thusly ends in themselves. P3 simply notes that the stipulation of this ethical theory is that one ought to be rational which implies being logically consistent; and P4 demonstrates that treating a person as solely a means towards an end entails (at least implicitly) a contradiction and thusly should not be done (if one is rational): when one uses another person for solely their own end, they concede in action that the other person is not an end in themselves (because they are treating them as solely a means) but are equally conceding that they are an end in themselves (due to their nature as a person)—hence the contradiction.
P1: If something is solely a means towards an end, then it is not an end in itself. — Bob Ross
This is a vacuous definition, not an ostensible claim.
P2: To value something entails it is solely a means towards an end.
Demonstrate this entailment.
…
C1: To value something entails it is not an end in itself.
Invalid inference from underdetermined "propositions". Ergo, "FET proof" (C6) fails.
"There is no fact that dictates God exists, but any sane person will agree to this judgement."
Claims like this beg challenges and can cause people to dismiss your claims outright. I'm not going to do that of course. I'm just noting that if you want to get to your point, you don't have to make claims like this. A simple "I'm not here to debate why one should choose the subjective start of, 'one ought to do what is rational.' I'm simply going to start with this and show a morality based on rationality." will work fine. So that's what I'm going to do. I'll assume that we take the prime assumption that we ought to act rationally and go from there.
P1: If something is solely a means towards an end, then it is not an end in itself.
P2: To value something entails it is solely a means towards an end.
C1: To value something entails it is not an end in itself. — Bob Ross
P1 is fine, but how do we get P2? Can I not value an end itself? If I valued world peace, would that not be the end of my means? Can you explain further what you mean by P2?
That is fine, but what if I don't value a mind? I'm assuming with the initial premise of "we ought to be rational" that "minds are rational, therefore they should be valued for they ought to be."
I'm a little confused by P5. Why are persons ends in themselves? Can't I use persons as means to my goals, even benevolently? If I send soldiers out to stop a terrorist, am I not using those soldiers, those people, as means to an end?
P1 merely highlights that if something is just a means towards some end (and just a means) then it cannot be an end itself—e.g., if mowing my lawn is a means towards making my house look presentable (and that being the only consideration), then mowing my lawn is solely means to an end and that end is making my house look presentable. P2 notes that persons (i.e., minds) are ends in themselves: persons are the only type of existence in reality which is capable of having ends and of being ultimately the final end for itself—e.g., although making my house look good may have been the end within the previous example’s context, it is likewise only a means toward another end (like making myself look respectable to my guests) but it will, without any consideration of other people as ends, ultimately bottom out at the final end of myself: I ultimately mow my lawn, in the case that I am not considering other people as ends, for myself—for my benefit. Persons are the only creators capable of setting out hypothetical imperatives (i.e., contextual ends) for the sake of themselves (as the final end) and are thusly ends in themselves. P3 simply notes that the stipulation of this ethical theory is that one ought to be rational which implies being logically consistent; and P4 demonstrates that treating a person as solely a means towards an end entails (at least implicitly) a contradiction and thusly should not be done (if one is rational): when one uses another person for solely their own end, they concede in action that the other person is not an end in themselves (because they are treating them as solely a means) but are equally conceding that they are an end in themselves (due to their nature as a person)—hence the contradiction.
That persons, and thus minds are means and not ends in themselves. This is because you haven't proven either of the statements, only asserted them. Still, lets continue and assume you can demonstrate C4 as true.
Again I'm going to assume minds have value because they are rational and therefore have innate value. So since we should not consider minds valueless, they have value. And since minds have value, people have value. But then doesn't this prove that people are not ends in themselves?
That we should consider that minds have value? Then why are we asserting that minds don't have value?
Are you stating that not valuing a mind with the representation of 0, is in fact a value? Because that just doesn't work Bob. The number zero is a representation of there not being a quantity. The number zero is not a quantity in itself. The number zero for value is a representation of there being no value, a numeric assignment of zero for value does not mean there exists a value. It means there is no underlying represented value.
Finally, the term 'invaluable' means that it has so much value, it cannot be quantified into one number. It doesn't mean it has no value at all.
I think you're trying to say something here, but its just not coming across correctly. It seems to me that when you speak about valuing something, you're talking about a quantative value. For example, lets say we valued a person's worth at 10,000 dollars. If of course we could value people quantitively, then we could use them as means to an end. For example, I could use a person worth 10,000 dollars to make myself 1 million dollars. However, if human value is so valuable as to be beyond quantification, an infinite value so to speak, then we could never use a human as a means to an end. We don't use infinite money to make infinite money, that's silly. We simply enjoy infinite money.
Is that what you were trying to say?
This seems to jive with your idea of your formula of ideal sovereignty. If all people are infinitely valuable, sacrificing one infinity for 99 infinities works in the moment of practical necessity, but one infinity is just as equivalent in value to 99 infinities, thus this sacrifice should be abated where possible.
That’s fair. It opens up the discussion back to metaethics; but I just wanted to make it clear that this theory was building off of the previous one, so one has to subjectively affirm ‘one ought to be rational’—there is not moral fact which makes it so. — Bob Ross
Persons are ends in themselves because they have the capacity to set out means towards ultimately themselves as the end; thusly, they are ends in themselves. — Bob Ross
If you don’t believe that persons are ends in themselves, then, of course, the conclusion will not follow. — Bob Ross
Firstly, I would just like to note again that I am not arguing that only rational agents have value, because I don not consider all minds to even have the capacity to be rational (in any meaningful sense); or, if they do, it is a stretch. — Bob Ross
Finally, the term 'invaluable' means that it has so much value, it cannot be quantified into one number. It doesn't mean it has no value at all.
That’s fair. I just mean by “we can’t value it” that we cannot put a price on it. — Bob Ross
That’s fair, and this is why I revised the argument. Hopefully it is a bit clearer now what it is arguing. — Bob Ross
I am trying to convey that persons are ends in themselves because their nature is such that they are the creators of values (they set out things as means towards their own ends, making them the end ultimately); and if we treat them solely as a means towards an end then we are implicitly conceding the contradiction that they are and are not an end in themselves. So if we are to be rational, then we cannot solely treat someone as means towards an end, but always simultaneously an end in themselves—hence FET. — Bob Ross
I understand from your point of view, but for the reader, its not relevant what your argument is here.
I could agree with you if you stated minds, which would include insects, animals, and potentially plants.
The only problem in the theory is proving why minds are invaluable. I happen to agree that minds are the highest values in existence, but for the theory to hold you'll need to prove why minds, even irrational ones, are priced right out of quantification.
1. Minds vs persons.
Can we justify killing an animal to eat it and survive if they are a means to us and an end to themself? If ends to themselves are invaluable, how do we justify killing and eating cows over killing and eating other humans?
The problem with removing value entirely is that questions of relative sacrifice no longer have any justification.
We have a room with 3 people. An unapologetic murderer, an unapologetic saint, and a regular person. They all must choose one of them to die for the other 2 to live. Currently, your theory has no means of stating that the murderer should be the one to die.
Anytime we run into a case that conflicts with what most people would innately feel is a simple moral choice and conclusion, the theory needs to clearly and persuasively explain why we should logically dismiss that conclusion.
How do we treat minds that believe the best end to itself, is to end other ends in themselves? Or believes it is rational that the worth of other minds can be quantified as less than its own mind?
Finally, after fully establishing how it minds and not persons that this theory applies to, I would study the general criticisms that people lobby against Kant and see if an how your theory answers or dodges those criticisms
I am talking about minds, as ‘persons’ to me is a ‘being with personhood’ which, in turns, just entails that the being ‘has a mind’. I did re-google of the term ‘person’ and it seems to exclusively tend to pertain to humans, so I will rewrite the argument with ‘mind’ instead of ‘person’ to more clearly convey the point. — Bob Ross
So, I got rid of that ‘value’ language in the argument because I don’t think it really matters. If you can’t treat an end as merely a means, then it doesn’t matter if you find it invaluable or not: you will treat it as though it is anyways.
So the argument is just FET, which is just that one cannot use a mind as solely a means towards an end but also must treat it simultaneously as an end in itself; and this is demonstrated in the (new) proof by teasing out a contradiction. — Bob Ross
Can we justify killing an animal to eat it and survive if they are a means to us and an end to themself? If ends to themselves are invaluable, how do we justify killing and eating cows over killing and eating other humans?
This is also addressed in the OP: my answer is yes if it is for the reason of nourishment, not things like taste. I can go through the argument if you would like for why that would be the case. This is another distinguishing factor between me and Kant. — Bob Ross
The problem with removing value entirely is that questions of relative sacrifice no longer have any justification.
— Bob Ross
If one is really taking FET seriously, then even in situations where they must violate it they should still be considering FIS which is a pragmatic formula that is centered around sanctity of minds, and it is a simple question: what action can I perform that would progress best towards a world with maximal sovereignty of minds (persons)? — Bob Ross
Anytime we run into a case that conflicts with what most people would innately feel is a simple moral choice and conclusion, the theory needs to clearly and persuasively explain why we should logically dismiss that conclusion.
I don’t think we should dismiss that conclusion at all. — Bob Ross
I don’t understand the first question, but my answer to the second is that they would be violating FET if they did all else being equal. If it is a moral antinomy, then they may be right depending on the facts in relation to FIS (in principle); but I would intuit that we would be regressing my removing human beings inalienable rights, so I would say in the case of humans we are best off (for the sake of getting to a maximal sovereignty state) to keep rights inalienable. — Bob Ross
Seems fine to me. Since this is based off of Kant, it might help to contrast your reasoning with why Kant chose rational minds. I explored Kant years ago and do not remember much at this point.
Also, an animal is not a person. So no need to go into any more detail for me.
So I think this is in a lot better place, I just noted two questions to consider.
1. Can you prove that any of us should care about people as ends in themselves?
2. Can you make a clear contrast with how Kant determines its rational beings to consider in the FET with your line of reasoning that it should be minds?
Other then that, I think its just Kant stuff, and I'm sure a Kantian will come along and be able to provide more feedback. Nicely done Bob!
It is because he considers only rational agents to have the sufficient freedom to obey their own representational laws as opposed to the laws of nature.
I say all minds have sufficient freedom to do it, we just don’t have the same amount each. — Bob Ross
#1 is proven by the argument for FET: if one is rational, then they cannot treat a mind as solely a means towards an end without conceding a contradiction. — Bob Ross
Do you agree, Philosophim, with FET and FIS? Or are you just granting them as internally coherent? — Bob Ross
I take a much more naturalistic approach: I say nature, especially evolution, makes no leaps. It is clear to me that the vast majority of animals (although I don’t know about literally all of them) have sufficient freedom to set out a means towards their end, even if they lack the highly rational capacities we humans have. My dog clearly is not rational, but she has her moments: if the matt is wet outside, then she will wait farther back for me to let her in so that her feet don’t get wet. That’s a deliberate action sparked by her making a free choice to not get her feet wet and trying to actualize that prevention by setting out waiting farther back as a means towards that end. Anyways, I am a compatiblist when it comes to free will and don’t believe in souls. — Bob Ross
I'm sure Mww will have a lot to say — Bob Ross
The only potential problem I see is how to justify eating or using animals for materials or labor
Beyond animals, there's now also the question of insects. Do they have minds?
Where does a mind begin and end?
If we can't treat them as solely means, then do we have a right to eat them?
Why are animals and insects ends in themselves but clearly have less value compared to people?
The only issue is that P2: Person's are ends in themselves isn't proven, its more of a given assumption.
But it all hinges on the reader accepting that a mind is an end in itself and that ends in themselves matter. For a person who already agrees or does not want to question this, it can work.
I'm granting them as acceptably internally coherent.
Its not that I don't think minds are the greatest things that can be, its the 'end in themselves' argument that isn't enough for me. Why is it important to be a end in itself? What does that even mean? (I know you've answered this, just showing my thought process) Why is it that we have value and morality at all?
….basing metaethics on F.P.M.M, 1785, isn’t what that treatise is about. For ethical systems, you’d probably want Metaphysics of Ethics,1797, especially considering your sections on rights and virtue, each having a book of their own in that work as a whole
….the exchange of rational beings for minds either leaves out, or at least makes no account for the fundamental predicates of Kantian moral/ethical philosophy, re: will, autonomy and pure practical reason belonging necessarily to the former as a rational being, or person, but these need methodological justification in the latter as a simple mind;
….the conceptions means and ends, as they relate to moral/ethical philosophy, need to be determined before a FET with them as its ground, makes sense;
….you say, “FET, no matter how useful it is itself for ethics, cannot be enough for good moral discernment”, but I rather think the intent of it was precisely for moral discernment, of the pure subjectivist account.
….lastly, if one thinks ethics relates to a community of persons/minds, wouldn’t each mind need a moral disposition of his own? Otherwise, they become a hive rather than a community. And if that’s the case, shouldn’t there be some necessary condition similar to a categorical imperative somewhere in this current theory?
Anyway, I like the work that’s been done here, but it seems a little incomplete to me. I can’t help but think that upon more substance amended to the conditions, it may be found they don’t work as they are now.
So, I would like to point out this is just an empirical question about what exactly has a mind, whereas my theory is simply proving that if it does have one — Bob Ross
Where does a mind begin and end?
I definitely can’t answer that, and, quite frankly, no one can. — Bob Ross
Why are animals and insects ends in themselves but clearly have less value compared to people?
They don’t have less value than humans: they are prioritized lower in the case of moral antinomies, which is most of practical life, than humans. — Bob Ross
The only issue is that P2: Person's are ends in themselves isn't proven, its more of a given assumption.
I added more sections that pertain to ends vs. means; and there is an explanation below the argument of why P2 is true. They are ends in themselves because they are the only beings with a nature such that they are an absolute end. — Bob Ross
Which premise do you disagree with? — Bob Ross
I see that as a problem considering that minds and their status are the fundamental lynch pin of your argument. Perhaps this could be answered if you define whether it is possible for something that is not a mind to be an end in itself.
I understand you don't want to use the word value, but almost anyone using the theory will. In the case of choosing what must be sacrificed for another species to live, there must be a rationale behind it. In your case if you want to avoid value, you may just want to say, "Whatever is stronger." So if an insect ate a human being, it would be merely due to capability and not that one is more valuable than the other.
I'm not seeing why that matters though. All this seems to imply is that minds are beings that are ends in themselves. It doesn't prove why anyone should value this, its just a claim.
…
Just why ends in themselves should matter beyond our desire or opinion that they should matter.
I see that as a problem considering that minds and their status are the fundamental lynch pin of your argument. Perhaps this could be answered if you define whether it is possible for something that is not a mind to be an end in itself.
I think this is just the fallacy of the heap. — Bob Ross
Likewise, it is not “the stronger wins”. It is entirely possible that, according to FIS, a mind holds higher precedence over another mind and the former is physically weaker than the latter. — Bob Ross
So if you accept that ‘one ought to be rational’ and that ‘minds are ends in themselves’ and that ‘sole means are not ends’, then it logically follows that one should not treat them as a mere means. — Bob Ross
I'm wondering if the tie in of minds to things in themselves is this fallacy. My thinking was that if minds are the only things that are ends in themselves, you can just remove ends in themselves and just note that minds are simply the things on this planet which should be protected and encouraged. It just simplifies the argument.
As a simple solution its a nice thought, but I'm not seeing how we can develop any air tight means of measurement when tough moral choices come up. Its not anything you have to debate with me about, these are just musings to think about.
So if you accept that ‘one ought to be rational’ and that ‘minds are ends in themselves’ and that ‘sole means are not ends’, then it logically follows that one should not treat them as a mere means. — Bob Ross
I get that. The question is why anyone should care if a mind thinks its an end to itself
There's nothing requiring me in that argument to not solely treat them as an ends in themselves. All you've noted is that we cannot solely view them as a means.
Vice versa it also means we cannot solely view them as an ends.
Is it possible that you could demonstrate why using a person for one's own end is a contradiction?
I believe you need to include Kant's universizability principle for it work.
What if I also treat myself as a means to an end?
1. It is required to note that minds are ends in themselves because the identity of ‘an absolute end’ does not entail itself that those are only minds — Bob Ross
FIS does not afford an equation that one can determine exactly what one should do in every given situation: it is a general formula, not an exact science. I have never heard a normative ethical theory that is able to afford such an equation without biting a lot of bullets. — Bob Ross
If one accepts that accepting the premises entails the conclusion that one should treat minds as sacred, then if they either have deny a premise or accept that they should treat mind as sacred. — Bob Ross
Repeating your definition doesn't make it more substantive than just a definition.If something is solely a means to an end, then it can’t be an end itself because it is just a means towards some other end. If it is also an end then it is not just a means towards an end. — Bob Ross
Again, an arbitrary posit..The argument for FET is as follows:
P1: If something is solely a means towards an end, then it is not an end in itself.
P2: Minds are ends in themselves.
[ ... ] — Bob Ross
Circular to the point of being tautological.P2 notes that minds are ends in themselves, and this is because minds are the only beings with the nature such that they are their own end—i.e., they are an absolute end
:roll:Minds are the only beings capable of setting out contextual ends for the sake of themselves (as the final, absolute end) and are thusly ends in themselves.
Again, this conclusion does not follow validly from your mere 'definitions' (& otherwise 'hidden premises' e.g. what is conceptually meant by "minds").C: One should not treat a mind as solely a means towards an end, but always as (at least) simultaneously an end in themselves.
1. It is required to note that minds are ends in themselves because the identity of ‘an absolute end’ does not entail itself that those are only minds — Bob Ross
This is why I asked earlier if you could give an example of an end in itself that wasn't a mind.
Yes, this is my general problem with ethical theories and why I feel we have a lot more work to do on the matter.
Right, but that's the answer to any valid syllogism. If we accept the premises, then the conclusion must necessarily be so. Yes, proving that first is essential. But after its proven, the question becomes, "Can you prove that I should accept your premises?"
Reason's Greetings & Happy New Year, Bob! :sparkle:
If something is solely a means to an end, then it can’t be an end itself because it is just a means towards some other end. If it is also an end then it is not just a means towards an end. — Bob Ross
Repeating your definition doesn't make it more substantive than just a definition.
P2 notes that minds are ends in themselves, and this is because minds are the only beings with the nature such that they are their own end—i.e., they are an absolute end
Circular to the point of being tautological.
C: One should not treat a mind as solely a means towards an end, but always as (at least) simultaneously an end in themselves.
Again, this conclusion does not follow validly from your mere 'definitions' (& otherwise 'hidden premises' e.g. what is conceptually meant by "minds").
There aren’t any: my point is just that I am predicating that only minds are ends-in-themselves and not equivocating them. — Bob Ross
So that’s what I was asking about before: which premise do you currently reject? We can discuss further whichever one that is. — Bob Ross
Stating that something is self-evident doesn't demonstrate that its also not an equivocation though. If minds are not identical to ends-in-themselves, then we would need to see some difference between a mind and an end-in-itself. If you aren't seeing equivocation, could you note how they are not simply the same thing?
For me it is that I should value an end in itself beyond an opinion that I should do so. I see nothing concrete that binds me to it, or demonstrates a provable ethical decision
A mind is an emergent process of a brain or a soul (take our pic) which is capable of having desires, cognizing, and having a conscious experience or an awareness of its environment; whereas, an end-in-itself is just a shorthand for something capable of deploying absolute ends. — Bob Ross
Ok, which premise then? — Bob Ross
P4: To treat a mind as solely a means towards an end is to contradict their nature — Bob Ross
Yes, but can you give an example of that 'something' that isn't a mind?
Contradicting a person's nature is not the law of non-contradiction.
Now, to be completely honest, I am rethinking this normative theory; because I don’t think it works anymore. I have this darn habit of writing something up, and quickly defeating my own position—back to the drawing board! ): — Bob Ross
The reason I don’t think it works is because I think the contradiction doesn’t actually exist if one disambiguates the language: kind of like how B and C were really easy to conflate in your theory, being an being with the ability to set out absolute ends is different than being an absolute end. — Bob Ross
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.