each valid sentence in the language of the axioms is then either true or false in the model. (It could be independent, too, but we're not concerned with that here). — fishfry
the OP makes the point that there are more mathematical truths than there are symbol strings to express them. — fishfry
I used to think that Carnap's theorem was the real culprit:
"For any property of logic sentences, there always exists a true sentence that does not have it, or a false sentence that has it, or both." — Tarskian
And that was my basic question: why having both addition and multiplication entail incompleteness?We know it is so because having both addition and multiplication entails incompleteness, so, since Presburger arithmetic is complete, it can't define multiplication. — TonesInDeepFreeze
why having both addition and multiplication entail incompleteness?
How does it entail incompleteness? — ssu
Is it that with both addition and multiplication you can make a diagonalization or what is the reason? — ssu
OK, I think you answered here my question.But we need multiplication for Godel numbering. — TonesInDeepFreeze
My favorite game on the internet is guessing the number of page views per day for math and other topics. I guessed 126 here, whereas it is 111. Close, but no cigar. — jgill
That's interesting. Which page views? I think you've mentioned in the past that you look at papers written or something like that. — fishfry
For perspective, keep in mind that Skolem arithmetic and Presburger arithmetic are not fully analagous, since Skolem arithmetic has more detailed axioms about its operation symbol. — TonesInDeepFreeze
Where did Carnap write that? — TonesInDeepFreeze
https://en.m.wikipedia.org/wiki/Diagonal_lemma
Rudolf Carnap (1934) was the first to prove the general self-referential lemma,[6] which says that for any formula F in a theory T satisfying certain conditions, there exists aformulasentence ψ such that ψ ↔ F(°#(ψ)) is provable in T.
Counterexample: Let P be the property: P(S) if and only if S is equivalent with S. — TonesInDeepFreeze
No, I meant what I wrote, I showed you a property of sentences that every sentence has.
And what you wrote doesn't even make sense. # S is a number not a sentence. — TonesInDeepFreeze
No, I meant what I wrote, I showed you a property of sentences that every sentence has. — TonesInDeepFreeze
For any property of logic sentences, there always exists a true sentence that does not have it, or a false sentence that has it, or both. — TonesInDeepFreeze
That doesn't mention PA. Rather, it a universal generalization over properties and sentences. — TonesInDeepFreeze
For certain theories T, for every formula F(x) there is a sentence S such that T |- S <-> F(r(#S)). — TonesInDeepFreeze
For certain theories T, for every formula F(x) there is a sentence S such that T |- S <-> ¬F(r(#S)).
(2) C generalizes over formulas, not over properties. — TonesInDeepFreeze
(3) C doesn't say anything about 'true'. — TonesInDeepFreeze
You said that my counterexample is not in PA. — TonesInDeepFreeze
Your quoted characterization did not have the specifications you are giving now. Your quoted characterization was a broad generalization about properties and sentences. — TonesInDeepFreeze
(2) PA doesn't say 'true' and 'false'. — TonesInDeepFreeze
(4) There are properties not expressed by formulas, so the generalization should be over formulas, not properties. — TonesInDeepFreeze
(S ∧ ¬F(r(#S)) ∨ (¬S ∧ F(r(#S))
Meaning:
(S is true and F is false) or (S is false and F is true)
Meaning:
A true sentence that does not have the property, or a false sentence that has the property, or both. — Tarskian
It is possible to precisely state all the conditions that apply, but in that case, the explanation becomes impenetrable. Nobody would be interested in a multidisciplinary forum. In order to keep it readable, there is no other alternative than to leave things out. — Tarskian
"S ∧ ¬F(r(#S)" is not the same as "S & ~F".
"¬S ∧ F(r(#S)" is not the same as "~S & F". — TonesInDeepFreeze
(S is true and F(r(#S)) is false) or (S is false and F(r(#S)) is true)
(S is true and F is false) and (S is false and F is true)
and lately, you confuse the predicate F with a sentence. — TonesInDeepFreeze
And I don't know why you would suppose that people would care about your synopsis of Carnap if they didn't also grasp the mathematical basis. — TonesInDeepFreeze
The truth of a sentence is per interpretation, not per axioms. — TonesInDeepFreeze
Some sentences are true in all models. Some sentences are true in no models. Some sentences are true in some models and not true in other models.
Axioms are sentences. Some axioms are true in all models (those are logical axioms). Some axioms are true in no models (those are logically false axioms, hence inconsistent, axioms). Some axioms are true in some models and not true in other models (those are typically mathematical axioms).
The key relationship between axioms and truth is: Every model in which the axioms are true is a model in which the theorems of the axioms are true. And every set of axioms induces the class of all and only those models in which the axioms are true. — TonesInDeepFreeze
(1) I would avoid the word 'valid' there, since it could be misunderstood in the more ordinary sense of 'valid' meaning 'true in every model'. What you mean is 'well-formed'. But, by definition, every sentence is well-formed, so we only need to say 'sentence'. — TonesInDeepFreeze
(2) If by 'independent' you mean 'not determined to be true, and not determined to be false', then there are no such sentences. Per a given model, a sentence is either true in the model or false in the model, and not both. — TonesInDeepFreeze
That depends on what things are truths.
If a truth is a true sentence, then there are exactly as many truths as there are true sentences, which is to say there are denumerably many
If a truth is "state-of-affairs", such as taken to be a relation on the universe, then, for an infinite universe, there are more "truths" then sentences. — TonesInDeepFreeze
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.