• Banno
    23.4k
    Some more curiosities from recent developments in logic. This video is most interesting:


    Logical laws are supposed to work in every case. Modus Tollens, non-contradiction, identity - these work in any and all cases. A logical nihilist will reject this.


    To be a law of logic, a principle must hold in complete generality
    No principle holds in complete generality
    ____________________
    There are no laws of logic.
    — Gillian Russell

    There are two ways to deal with this argument.

    A logical monist will take the option of rejecting the conclusion, and also the second premise. For them the laws of logic hold with complete generality.

    A logical pluralist will reject the conclusion and the first premise. For them laws of logic apply to discreet languages within logic, not to the whole of language. Classical logic, for example, is that part of language in which propositions have only two values, true or false. Other paraconsistent and paracomplete logics might be applied elsewhere.

    A few counter-examples of logical principles that might be thought to apply everywhere.

    Identity: ϑ ⊧ ϑ; but consider "this is the first time I have used this sentence in this paragraph, therefore this is the first time I have used this sentence in this paragraph"

    And elimination: ϑ & ϒ ⊧ ϑ; But consider "ϑ is true only if it is part of a conjunction".

    Other and tighter examples can be found in the video.

    Especially appealing is the application of Lakatos' method to logic; choosing logical pluralism over logical monism leads to more fruitful discussions.
  • tim wood
    8.7k
    I can't make out a lot of what she's saying or writing, and compared with MIT math lectures of which numerous are on Youtube, this is a difficult hear/watch. Also, there seemed no meat, almost like a class in psychology where ideas are thrown out, and you can take only those you fancy.

    Are you able to briefly fill in a little bit?

    Taking logic to be manipulation of symbols according to rules, then monism would seem right.

    Taking logic as an attempt to wrangle language, then it seems reasonable that there might be different logics - pluralism. Although monistic within each logic, yes?

    Logical nihilism seems nonsensical. What would be the point? Would not I be able to prove with nihilistic logic that everyone on the planet owes me USD20? And please pay up? But this is taking nihilism as no rules. Or does it mean merely that any one logic, or any set of logics, is in error? I.e., that there are any number of good rules, but applying them is problematic.

    In short, lacking definiteness, I could not make out any points. Although I did appreciate her starting out with some basic definitions.

    Puts you to dog's work, to retrieve what of substance she may have said. But the best I could make of it was her saying, "Some people think this; some people think that." I'd like to think there's a lot more to it, and one hopes not too difficult recover at least some of it.
  • Tom Storm
    8.4k
    This is very interesting even to a non-philosopher - if I get time I will check out the video after work. I've been a logical monist but to be honest I have not interrogated these axioms as much as I could have. The notion of choosing logical pluralism over logical monism is enticing. Thanks.

    I'm assuming the idea is that identity, non-contradiction and excluded middle remain tautologies but are less certain even if it is generally held that these are the preconditions for sensible communication.
  • Banno
    23.4k


    I found it fairly clear. But here's the article from which it derives.

    https://gilliankrussell.files.wordpress.com/2018/05/logicalnihilism-philissues-v3.pdf
  • Banno
    23.4k
    Also, see Logical Pluralism on Stanford.
  • 180 Proof
    14.1k
    To be a law of logic, a principle must hold in complete generality
    No principle holds in complete generality
    ____________________
    There are no laws of logic.
    — Gillian Russell
    Banno
    So this conclusion is not a law of logic. Okay.

    Nothing to see here, move along.

    What?

    Mathematics in its entirety lacks a foundation. Yep.

    Spill on aisle Real Number.

    Sorry, Prof. Russell, I'm an embodied cognitivist with respect to abstract formal constructs.
  • Cuthbert
    1.1k
    Identity: ϑ ⊧ ϑ; but consider "this is the first time I have used this sentence in this paragraph, therefore this is the first time I have used this sentence in this paragraph"

    I'm looking forward to the video at leisure but this leapt out for attention. Isn't it an indexical (context-dependent) utterance? The second utterance expresses a different proposition from the first - so they are not identical propositions and we would not expect identity to hold. The expression "this sentence" refers to a different sentence in the first utterance from the second.

    (Just as my saying "I am Cuthbert" expresses a different proposition from someone else's saying "I am Cuthbert", which explains why the same utterance can be either true or false depending upon context.)

    But there's only one sentence. Ah. Shut ma mouth. I will watch the video. I know it's all a trick, though, so I'm not going to be taken in. Not that I'm prejudiced, of course.
  • Banno
    23.4k
    Yep. That's dealt with in the video, at the end. The the monster-barring response?
  • Cuthbert
    1.1k
    Fingers in ears, la-la-la. Looking forward to it but I'm supposed to be 'working from home' right now.....
  • Corvus
    3k
    Looks like a really interesting video. Only watched first 8 minutes, but sounds inspiring. I am always interested in some new or different view point on the subject or topics. Will bookmark and watch the whole lot either tonight or this weekend. Thanks for sharing. :up:
  • TheMadFool
    13.8k
    To be a law of logic, a principle must hold in complete generality
    No principle holds in complete generality
    ____________________
    There are no laws of logic.
    — Gillian Russell

    What about if I apply the conclusion (There are no laws of logic) to Gillian Russell's argument? The argument seems to be self-refuting - it relies on the laws of logic i.e. it assumes there are laws of logic but claims there are no laws of logic. Contradiction! Gillian Russell is contradicting herself full tilt.

    Logic can't be used to negate itself for to do that is to affirm itself. Contradiction!
  • Banno
    23.4k
    Dealt with a few minutes into the video.
  • Banno
    23.4k
    Fingers in ears, la-la-la. Looking forward to it but I'm supposed to be 'working from home' right now.....Cuthbert

    :grin: You poor bugger. Feel for you.

    Have a look when you have time - and see the article cited, too. It's curious stuff. There's something going on.
  • TheMadFool
    13.8k
    Deal with a few minutes into the video.Banno

    Roger!
  • tim wood
    8.7k
    Thank you.

    From p. 14. "Lemma incorporation is also preferable to monster-barring. Monster-barring
    requires us to read implausible restrictions back into ‘interpretation’ in our original definition of logical consequence, and it fails to use the opportunity presented by the monsters to learn more. Lemma incorporation, by contrast, refines the original proofs in response to the counterexamples, and the results
    then naturally suggest new avenues of research."

    :100:

    From p. 6 of Banno's reference. "A nihilist can take the same approach to every putative logical law that these friends of weak logics take to the classical laws they have abandoned: they aren’t really laws, perhaps because of quite rare and esoteric counterexamples. But the principles will do just fine in many contexts. Perhaps all the standard instances f conjunction introduction are truth-preserving. The nihilist can allow this, so long as she thinks there are some—perhaps very specialised—cases in which it fails."

    [And footnote 13] "13 This also explains how it is possible to give an argument for logical nihilism, without the view itself undermining that argument; each of the steps in the argument might be truth preserving without it being the case that all arguments of that form are truth-preserving."

    -----------------------------------

    Above I suggested that with nihilistic logic I can prove you (gentle reader) owe me $20. Apparently the remedies for such nonsense are 1) to bar such proofs as "monsters", or 2) ,and apparently preferably, to incorporate the argument as a lemma, called lemma incorporation, and make a new logic.

    Anyone see problems with this? If nothing else there are going to be a lot, a way lot, of new lemmas. If logic is the application of rules, how can they be applied if there are so many they cannot even in principle be consulted?

    Or if I can prove you owe, you can prove you don't. That is, every proposition can be upended, and footnote 13 above is a dead letter.

    And I object to the side-slippage that blurs distinctions between truth and validity. Failure to keep these separated and apart each in its own cage is a beginning of trouble.
  • Joshs
    5.2k
    Do you think Lalatos’ approach to the logical proof is consistent with the later Wittgenstein? I wonder i particularly about the notion of truth , as opposed to usefulness , with regard to logical
    proof.
  • bongo fury
    1.6k
    But what all those people (Quine, Williamson, Preist, Kleene...) have in common is they think there's one logic, and, the one they like, that's the one.2:10

    Really? We can assume they are all monist, which I'm hoping will gloss as absolutist? I.e. not tolerant, or relativist, inasmuch as (not) regarding logics as horses for courses? [Thought I could safely use this figure without implying anything was a race, nvm.]

    I can see how someone of that persuasion (far more prevalent than I knew) might survey the totality of courses and decide that the only horse suitable is Humpty Dumpty, or worse. But a pluralist (relativist? or am I unaware of a recognised distinction?) already allows such a choice for a slowest [having fewest laws] variety of horse:

      [1] Tell me, do you think that a language game that assumes no logical law whatsoever deserves to be called a logic?

      [2] Perhaps not, but it's moot, because either it or a game with precisely one such law will definitely be a very weakest logic. Granted, 'weak logic' has the flavour of an oxymoron, but its instances clearly have at least mathematical interest, and might include also certain poetry, music, mime etc. What's the big deal?

      [1] Ah, but the trouble is, I'm assuming that: to be a law of logic, a principle must hold in complete generality. You say 'horses for courses' so you probably don't agree?

      [2] Relative to the totality of courses, guilty as charged. Only an absolutist, who didn't appreciate that truth is relative to a discourse, would agree. But on a course, in a discourse, which is good enough, a principle will indeed hold in complete generality if I call it logical. That's what I mean by logical: completely general (within the discourse) in governing inference from one statement to another.


    70
  • Banno
    23.4k
    Someone the other day said of "The Selfish Gene" that it was most influential amongst those who had read only the title.

    I wonder if that is true to some extent here, too.
  • Banno
    23.4k
    I'm an embodied cognitivist with respect to abstract formal constructs.180 Proof

    So, pretty much, am I. I don't see any prima facie contradiction between the two. Embodied cognitivism does not rule out abstract formal constructs.

    The horse will win, or not. There are no other options. So binary logic is applicable.
  • Banno
    23.4k
    Lakatos is known mostly as the foil for Feyerabend's anarchic method. So the obvious choice would be to address Feyerabend's criticism of Lakatos' strategy to this instance. That might be what you have in mind, but we might make it explicit. I don't think Feyerabend addressed the Euler example directly -I checked the indexes of both Against Method and Science in a free society and found no mention.

    But these would be odd bedfellows, since it seems clear that Feyerabend would side with the logical nihilists against both logical monism and Russell.

    My suspicion is that Feyerabend would treat binary logic as a natural interpretation, as so closely connected with the craft of logic as "to need a special effort to realise their existence and to determine their content" (Ch 6 of Against Method).

    We are left with the critique found in Chapter 16, that Lakatos' method is disguised anarchy. On this account lemma incorporation and monster barring are equally valid, the choice being arbitrary - at best an aesthetic or moral preference.

    Curiously Russell has another published article arguing that logic is not normative. Unfortunatly I have not been able to access it.

    So Logical Nihilism has me returning to what I had taken as pretty much settled; that scientific progress does not result from a more or less algorithmic method - induction, falsification and so one - but is instead the result of certain sorts of liberal social interaction - of moral and aesthetic choice.

    And this is why the article is worthy of consideration. It's ramifications are broad.
  • Cheshire
    1k
    You had me up to the conclusion. Perhaps there is no perfect source of knowledge; which so happens to include logic. It doesn't mean logic is an unreliable tool, because that would require logic.
    So Logical Nihilism has me returning to what I had taken as pretty much settled; that scientific progress does not result from a more or less algorithmic method - induction, falsification and so one - but is instead the result of certain sorts of liberal social interaction - of moral and aesthetic choice.Banno
    Seems to be your work. I wasn't going to suppose being worthy of certiorari.
  • Banno
    23.4k
    And elimination: ϑ & ϒ ⊧ ϑ; But consider "ϑ is true only if it is part of a conjunction".Banno
    No one addressed this; I think it quite funny. So I'll spell it out.

    1. This sentence is true only if it is not part of a compound sentence

    2. Snow is white

    therefore, since 1) stands alone, and snow is indeed white, both premises are true. So by &-introduction:

    3. This sentence is true only if it is not part of a compound sentence and snow is white

    ...which is false, since "This sentence is true only if it is not part of a compound sentence" now occurs in a compound sentence. (A compound sentence is formed by adding two independent clauses together using a conjunction.

    This is a variant on SOLO from p.9.

    So who will bar the monster, and who will befriend him?
  • Banno
    23.4k
    TO whom is this addressed, and to which conclusion?
  • Cheshire
    1k
    Edited to taste.
  • Banno
    23.4k
    Watching an adroit logician play with this stuff is like watching an talented musician; they know the rules, but break them intentionally in order to keep it interesting.
  • Tom Storm
    8.4k
    Watching an adroit logician play with this stuff is like watching an talented musician; they know the rules, but break them intentionally in order to keep it interesting.Banno

    Not unlike jazz improv.
  • Banno
    23.4k
    Yep, except I'm not keen on jazz. Too many words.

    Edit: Taking that further, jazz can be cleverness that hides ugliness. I suppose on that account Russell' s work might be seen as clever but ugly. Perhaps that is what the objection is.
  • Banno
    23.4k
    , @180 Proof Starting at 16:41

    "Arguments can be good in all kinds of ways even when they are not logically valid".

    But also, "If someone gives you a classically valid argument for the view that there are no valid arguments, that ought to be seriously worrying to someone who accepts classical logic".

    ...and then the discussion of modus ponens. How confident are you that there are no counter instances? But note, from the article, that logical nihilism is not the view that there are no logical truths; it is the view that there are always counter instances:
    if all it took to be a logical nihilist was commitment to the view that there are no logical truths, then some logicians who would not regard themselves as nihilists—and don’t seem to deserve the title—would get counted as such. For example, Strong Kleene logic is a logic on which there are no logical truths, though modus ponens and disjunctive syllogism both hold.7 It seems wrong to classify Strong Kleene logicians as logical nihilists.
  • Banno
    23.4k
    2 Towards logical nihilism
    Russell invents what we might call a ladder of interpretation, starting with a single interpretation, then two, three, and presumably so on.

    On a single interpretation, "T", the fallacy assuming the consequent is true. Sot he only way to avoid AC being a logical law is to widen the interpretation to include "F"...

    AC looks like a logical law because the interpretation is limited.

    Russell asks why we should not apply this reasoning to the law of excluded middle. Why not similarly conclude that it only looks like a logical law because we arbitrarily limit the interpretations to "T" or "F"?

    Expanding the "library of interpretations" provides similar counterexamples for various other supposed logical laws.
  • TheMadFool
    13.8k
    First off, a confession - I haven't had time to watch the video so what I'm about to say might change after.

    Starting at 16:41

    "Arguments can be good in all kinds of ways even when they are not logically valid".
    Banno

    What's Gillian Russell's citeria of a good argument? Whatever it is, it doesn't seem to be about validity and if not, how does she know the conclusion is true given some premises are?

    Her issue seems to be with deductive logic (validity above) but then she isn't saying anything we already don't know - there are cogent inductive arguments that aren't deductively valid - the conclusion is probable but not necessary.

    1. 99.99% of Indians are mathematcian = M
    2. Y is an Indian = I
    Ergo,
    3. Y is a mathematician = Y

    In modus ponens (the sticking point insofar as the OP is concerned) form the inductive argument looks like:

    4. If (M & I) then Y
    5. M & I
    Ergo,
    6. Y

    As you can see, statement 4 even if it isn't completely true, it's truer than false. Let's just say you would bet big on it.

    However, 6 doesn't follow deductively from 4 and 5 i.e. it's invalid but still, and notably, the argument is good.
  • Banno
    23.4k
    I haven't had time to watch the video so what I'm about to say might change after.TheMadFool

    Do that, then. Or read the article.
bold
italic
underline
strike
code
quote
ulist
image
url
mention
reveal
youtube
tweet
Add a Comment

Welcome to The Philosophy Forum!

Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.