No need to talk in terms of "qualia" or "quale". — creativesoul
But those meaningful correlations might include the coffee being better when you drink it and the cat being black on a white mat. — Marchesk
Just why and account of just what is materialism "self-denying and life-demeaning"? And then what's the alternative exactly? Those are the two questions that critics of materialism never seem to be able to answer. — Janus
It IS possible, as long as he does not deny the existence and importance of his own mind.The question is why is it not possible for a materialist to hold spiritual, ethical and aesthetical values? — Janus
(1) Environmental hidden states underdetermine perceptual feature formation.
(2) Bodily hidden states underdetermine perceptual feature formation.
(3) Task parameters underdetermine perceptual feature formation.
(4) Priors underdetermine perceptual feature formation. — fdrake
How does that work for animals? Fear and aggression are important for survival, and they're not exactly querying themselves for reports on conscious experiences. — Marchesk
Also in the moment when someone punches me, I'm probably reacting in anger, not stopping to do some reflection. That comes after the reaction. — Marchesk
I fully endorse what Dr. Seth is doing. — Marchesk
So does this mean other animals do not have experiences of colors, tastes, memories, because they lack the language to ask themselves about how other animals typically react? — Marchesk
Thinking about this some more, how would the words "afraid", "red" or "pain" have become part of language if there wasn't fear, color, or uncomfortable sensations to begin with? What exactly is the public model that we learn based on? — Marchesk
Translating it back to make sure we're concordant: the priors=flippers, task parameters =pegs and the strength of the trigger = hidden states. — fdrake
I think what I claimed is a bit stronger, it isn't just that the hidden state variables act as a sufficient cause for perceptual features to form (given task parameters and priors), I was also claiming that the value of the hidden states acts as a sufficient cause for the content of those formed perceptual features. So if I touch something at 100 degrees celcius (hidden state value), it will feel hot (content of perceptual feature). — fdrake
in order for the perceptual features it forms to be fit for purpose representations of the hidden states, whatever means of representation has to link the hidden state values with the perceptual feature content. If generically/ceteris paribus there failed to be a relationship between the hidden states and perceptual features with that character, perception wouldn't be a pragmatic modelling process. — fdrake
Let's take showing someone a picture of a duck. Even if they hadn't seen anything like a duck before, they would be able to demarcate the duck from whatever background it was on and would see roughly the same features; they'd see the wing bits, the bill, the long neck etc. That can be thought of splitting up patterns of (visual?) stimuli into chunks regardless of whether the chunks are named, interpreted, felt about etc. The evidence for that comes in two parts: firstly that the parts of the brain that it is known do abstract language stuff activate later than the object recognition parts that chunk the sensory stimuli up in the first place, and secondly that it would be such an inefficient strategy to require the brain have a unique "duck" category in order to recognise the duck as a distinct feature of the picture. IE, it is implausible that seeing a duck as a duck is required to see the object in the picture that others would see as the duck. — fdrake
That indicates that the elicited data is averaged and modelled somehow, and what we see - the picture - emerges from that ludicrously complicated series of hidden state data (and priors + task parameters). But what is the duration of a perceptual event of seeing such a face? If it were quicker than it takes to form a brief fixation on the image, we wouldn't see the whole face. Similarly, people forage the face picture for what is expected to be informative new content based on what fixations they've already made - eg if someone sees one eye, they look for another and maybe pass over the nose. So it seems the time period the model is updating, eliciting and promoting new actions in is sufficiently short that it does so within fixations. — fdrake
But that makes the aggregate perceptual feature of the face no longer neatly correspond to a single "global state"/global update of the model - because from before it is updating at least some parts of it during brief fixations, and the information content of brief fixations are a component part of the aggregate perceptual feature of someone's face. — fdrake
What that establishes is that salience and ongoing categorisation of sensory stimuli are highly influential in promoting actions during the environmental exploration that generates the stable features of our perception.
So it seems that the temporal ordering of dorsal and ventral signals doesn't block the influence of salience and categorisation on promoting exploratory actions — fdrake
So it seems that the temporal ordering of dorsal and ventral signals doesn't block the influence of salience and categorisation on promoting exploratory actions; and if they are ordered in that manner within a single update step, that ordering does not necessarily transfer to an ordering on those signal types within a single perceptual event - there can be feedback between them if there are multiple update steps, and feedforwards from previous update steps which indeed have had such cultural influences. — fdrake
The extent to which language use influences the emerging perceptual landscape will be at least the extent to which language use modifies and shapes the salience and categorisation components that inform the promotion of exploratory behaviours. What goes into that promotion need not be accrued within the perceptual event or a single model update. That dependence on prior and task parameters leaves a lot of room for language use (and other cultural effects) to play a strong role in shaping the emergence of perceptual features. — fdrake
We're not going to get anywhere in his stated project if you just insist that whatever you feel is happening is what's actually happening. — Isaac
In order to map brain states to phenomenological reports, you have to accept what neuroscientists are saying about brain states, otherwise you're saying phenomenological reports are infallible in a way the neuroscience isn't. — Isaac
So neuroscience says there is not an identifiable neural correlate for anger - we've looked really hard and can't find one. You've two choices 1) insist that because it feels like there must be one to you then that's the case and neuroscience just isn't trying hard enough, or 2) accept that something feeling like it's the case is not necessarily proof that it is, in fact, the case and work out how those feelings might have come about. — Isaac
I'm not entirely sure what you mean here. — Isaac
The model they use to handle the banana (knowing his soft it is, how heavy...) is informed by priors from the entire previous experience, but at the time of the perception event (thinking about a cortical level higher than a single saccade here), the two are not connected. — Isaac
As I said to Khaled, if you're of the former persuasion, there's no point in us talking (there's no point in talking to anyone). If you're just going to assume that the way things seem to you to be is the way they actually are regardless of any evidence to the contrary, then there's no point in seeking other views is there? — Isaac
I'm left with the impression that you and I both hold that fear is the only innate emotion. — creativesoul
Although anger and aggression can have wide-ranging consequences for social interactions, there is sparse knowledge as to which brain activations underlie the feelings of anger and the regulation of related punishment behaviors. To address these issues, we studied brain activity while participants played an economic interaction paradigm called Inequality Game (IG). The current study confirms that the IG elicits anger through the competitive behavior of an unfair (versus fair) other and promotes punishment behavior. Critically, when participants see the face of the unfair other, self-reported anger is parametrically related to activations in temporal areas and amygdala – regions typically associated with mentalizing and emotion processing, respectively. During anger provocation, activations in the dorsolateral prefrontal cortex, an area important for regulating emotions, predicted the inhibition of later punishment behavior. When participants subsequently engaged in behavioral decisions for the unfair versus fair other, increased activations were observed in regions involved in behavioral adjustment and social cognition, comprising posterior cingulate cortex, temporal cortex, and precuneus. These data point to a distinction of brain activations related to angry feelings and the control of subsequent behavioral choices. Furthermore, they show a contribution of prefrontal control mechanisms during anger provocation to the inhibition of later punishment.
https://www.nature.com/articles/s41598-018-28863-3 — Distinct Brain Areas involved in Anger versus Punishment during Social Interactions
Similarly, in the 1980s, psychologist Robert Plutchik identified eight basic emotions which he grouped into pairs of opposites, including joy and sadness, anger and fear, trust and disgust, and surprise and anticipation. This classification is known as a wheel of emotions and can be compared to a color wheel in that certain emotions mixed together can create new complex emotions.
More recently, a new study from the Institute of Neuroscience and Psychology at the University of Glasgow in 2014 found that instead of six, there may only be four easily recognizable basic emotions. The study discovered that anger and disgust shared similar facial expressions, as did surprise and fear. This suggests that the differences between those emotions are sociologically-based and not biologically-based. Despite all the conflicting research and adaptations, most research acknowledge that there are a set of universal basic emotions with recognizable facial features.
https://online.uwa.edu/news/emotional-psychology/#:~:text=According%20to%20the%20American%20Psychological,situations%20they%20find%20personally%20significant. — The Science Of Emotion: Exploring The Basics Of Emotional Psychology
So neuroscience says there is not an identifiable neural correlate for anger - we've looked really hard and can't find one. — Isaac
ARE there really beliefs? Or are we learning (from neuroscience and psychology, presumably) that, strictly speaking, beliefs are figments of our imagination, items in a superseded ontology? Philosophers generally regard such ontological questions as admitting just two possible answers: either beliefs exist or they do not. There is no such state as quasi existence; there are no stable doctrines of semi realism. Beliefs must either be vindicated along with the viruses or banished along with the banshees. A bracing conviction prevails, then, to the effect that when it comes to beliefs (and other mental items) one must be either a realist or an eliminative materialist. — Real Patterns
When are the elements of a pattern real and not merely apparent? Answering this question will help us resolve the misconceptions that have led to the proliferation of "ontological positions" about beliefs, the different grades or kinds of realism. I shall concentrate on five salient exemplars arrayed in the space of possibilities: Fodor's industrial-strength Realism (he writes it with a capital 'R'); Davidson's regular strength realism; my mild realism; Richard Rorty's milder than-mild irrealism, according to which the pattern is only in the eyes of the beholders, and Paul Churchland's eliminative materialism, which denies the reality of beliefs altogether. — Real Patterns
We're not going to get anywhere in his stated project if you just insist that whatever you feel is happening is what's actually happening. — Isaac
if you were Dennett, how would you counter this? — frank
Khaled's picture of what is going on prevents him form seeing the obvious falsehood. We have a person who says things such as "being scared is the experience you have on a horror ride" and "I am unable to feel scared because I have urbach-wiethe disease", but Khaled is obligated by his mistaken picture of mind to say that this person does not know of what they speak. — Banno
It is in that colloquial sense that I mean that the person who can't experience fear doesn't know what fear is, I don't mean to say they can't forumalte sentences with the word. — khaled
Good question. I would as soon doubt the existence of neuroscience as I would anger. — Marchesk
So neuroscience says there is not an identifiable neural correlate for anger - we've looked really hard and can't find one. You've two choices 1) insist that because it feels like there must be one to you then that's the case and neuroscience just isn't trying hard enough, or 2) accept that something feeling like it's the case is not necessarily proof that it is, in fact, the case and work out how those feelings might have come about.
As I said to Khaled, if you're of the former persuasion, there's no point in us talking (there's no point in talking to anyone). If you're just going to assume that the way things seem to you to be is the way they actually are regardless of any evidence to the contrary, then there's no point in seeking other views is there? — Isaac
Seeing as you already agree with that (I think) and I was addressing a misinterpretation — fdrake
If salience and categorisation do influence both dorsal and ventral signals even in the dorsal/ventral severing case, and language can influence both those signals, is the point you're making that language and culture only effect the integration of both streams because they're particularly high order processes? — fdrake
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.