Remind me of the defs. A section is a right inverse as I understand it. There can be a lot of right inverses to a function, you just keep choosing different elements in the preimages of points. Is that the bundle? — fishfry
there is no definition of the "meaning" of a theorem, and many mathematicians (starting from Hilbert, I guess) think that there is no point in trying to identify the "meaning" as something different from a list of symbols. — Mephist
Yes! I should have added a formal definition, but I have an aversion to writing symbols on this site :confused: I added a link with a clear picture, I think. — Mephist
May I ask you a question? How does one come to know this material and not have heard of measure theory? — fishfry
But now I am too curious: which theorems did you prove? — Mephist
No, I like "normal" mathematics: no computers involved. But having a theorem-prover as Coq to be able to verify if you can really write a proof of what you think is provable is very helpful. — Mephist
Where does measure theory (surely not taught in high school) intersect any of this? I've used it in various integration processes, the most interesting being functional integration. And Feynman constructed his sum of paths integral in more or less that concept. — jgill
Remind me of the defs. A section is a right inverse as I understand it. There can be a lot of right inverses to a function, you just keep choosing different elements in the preimages of points. Is that the bundle?
— fishfry
Yes. — Mephist
Now, a section of the fiber bundle (https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Section_(fiber_bundle)) is what in type theory is called a "dependently typed function", that from the point of view of logic is interpreted as the proof of a proposition with a free variable x: the fiber bundle is the proposition (that depends on x) and a section of that fiber bundle is a proof of that proposition. — Mephist
Probably you think that I completely missed the "meaning" of what a mathematical proof. But that's the way computers (formal logic systems) see proofs. I agree that the formal part is not all there is in it. Just take a look at this discussion, for example: — Mephist
So, you can describe algebrically what is the intersection and the disjoint union of sets (as product and sum of objects), what is a subset, what is the powerset of a set (an exponential), etc.
The interesting part is that you can describe what are propositions and logical operators completely in terms of objects and arrows, only by assuming the existence of an object with some particular properties, called "subobject classifier". This is NOT the same thing as homotopy type theory, where you build a formal logic system in the usual way: by building strings of symbols with given rules. Here you describe logical operations and propositions in terms of universal mapping properties, as you do with operations between sets. The subobject classifier is the object that represents the "set of all the propositions", and the implications between these propositions are arrows that start and end in this object. Even the logical quantifiers forall and exists are only two particular arrows. Basically, everything is defined in terms of universal mapping properties.
I don't know which details should I add. What part of topos theory do you want me to explain? — Mephist
think that you are ascribing to mathematics the kind of role that I don't think it has. At least, not directly. Or maybe I did walk into this when elaborating over my example. Its aim wasn't to model the structure of physical objects, but to illustrate how coarse structures not literally represented by mathematical ideals, can still be usefully approximated by those ideals. It was designed to have some similarity with the atomic structure of materials. — simeonz
The idea was, that actual physical structures approximate the mathematical ideals, and our numerical algorithms approximate those same ideals, and thus, under certain assumptions of the magnitudes of the involved deviations, our numerical algorithms match the physical structures within the required precision. — simeonz
P.S. I want to clarify that I do actually think that our computational and logical ideals are naturally inspired. They are not literally representative of any particular physical structure, but they are "seeded" as concepts by nature, whether our sentience existed or not. — simeonz
I can't see this. Can you give an example? — fishfry
.. . . believe that mathematical principles are always developed for purposes, goals, ends, and therefore . . . — Metaphysician Undercover
A section is a proof ... a section is a proof. I can't quite see that. I know that a section is a right inverse of a function. For example if f(x)=x2f(x)=x2 then a section is a function that, for each nonnegative real, picks out one of its plus or minus square roots. Is that about right? The section is the right inverse, so it's essentially a choice function on the collection of inverse images of all the points. Do I have that right? How does that become a proof? — fishfry
- We know that we cannot enumerate all halting Turing machines, so for every supposedly complete list of halting Turing machines I can find another halting Turing machine that is not in the list.
Does that mean that the set of halting Turing machines in uncountable? No! It only means that there is no way to enumerate that list!. — Mephist
Maybe I am not on the same page with you here. Before I try to answer in any detail, I have to get clear on the substance of our conversation. Are you saying that you imagine a system of computations which does not involve algebraic numbers, and either has the same utility for our industrial and daily applications at a discount computational cost, or enhances our conventional applications at no additional computational cost? Or do you mean that the use of irrational numbers is conceptually inaccurate with respect to a first-principles analysis of physics? If the latter, as I said, I don't think that it matters for mathematics.The physicist applying mathematical principles believes that the "materials" of mathematical ideals are a good approximation of the "materials" involved in actual physical structures, when in reality they are not. — Metaphysician Undercover
Sorry, I thought it was easier: I wanted to show you the complete structure of the category representing the proof of the proposition "2 > 0" derived from "forall x, s(x) > x" and "forall x, x > 0" but I didn't realize that it would take me ages to describe it in this way... and at the end it will be impossible to read. In Coq this is several lines of code, but is build automatically from a couple of commands. In reality, I never look at the real terms representing the proofs: they are built automatically. But I see that it would be a pain to build them by hand in this way! — Mephist
I have to find a better way to give you a description of how it's made without writing all the details.. — Mephist
Let me just give you just some examples: "x >= 3" is a fibration from the object Nat to the subobject classifier Prop. — Mephist
* What is Prop? Is it the category of propositions? Is it an object in some other category? And in what way is it a subobject classifier, analogous to {T, F} in ordinary logic? — fishfry
Can I ask your background again? Now I'm thinking that maybe you learned Coq but don't know the larger context of all these ideas. This is frustrating at my end. I can't tell if you know what you're talking about or if you just read a lot of Wiki pages. That's not meant to be provocative. Only that you are not communicating to me at all. And like I say I know this because I did my mathematical homework last night re sheaf theory. — fishfry
Well, if you want the exact definition of sheaf I can copy it from the book on category theory that I posted you yesterday. I don't know all possible examples (algebraic structures) of sheaves, that's for sure! I was thinking that we were speaking about the relation between topology and logic. My background is mainly in logic and computer science. — Mephist
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.