• _db
    3.6k
    What follows is a theory of ethics (created by myself), alongside applications of this theory in regards to the ethics of birth.

    -----

    The absence of pleasure is not-bad, and the absence of pain is not-good. This goes against the asymmetry presented by Benatar that is criticized by Cabrera (whom I agree with). The absence of pain is only good (and the absence of pleasure is only bad) when utilizing counterfactuals. By doing so, we put the interests of possible beings into consideration.

    Would they want to experience [insert medical condition here]? Would they want to experience desire and endless striving? Would they want to experience death? Would they want to experience the limitless sufferings of Hell (if it exists)? Of course not - in which case, the absence of these negatives is good only because they have been avoided.

    Would they want to experience [insert joyous occasion here]? Would they want to experience orgasms? Would they want to experience the limitless omega-sequence of Heaven (if it exists)? Of course they would – in which case, the absence of these positives is bad only because they have been avoided.

    So this is the logical symmetry. But something doesn’t feel right. Is the absence of pleasure really a bad thing? Logically, it must be a bad thing. But intuitively, it’s not. We don’t feel compelled to give someone pleasure, but we certainly feel compelled not to give someone pain.

    -----

    But hold on, again! This isn’t quite right, either. For what if you could, at a press of a button, bring millions of people into existence that experience limitless joy. You only have five minutes to do this, and then your chance is over. It’s intuitive that by not pressing the button, you’d be preventing these individuals from experiencing pleasure. You might even feel a bit of guilt for not allowing these people to experience this joy. By not pressing the button, you have taken away all chance of their happiness.

    Now of course, nobody is actually there to experience this deprivation. Objectively nothing has changed. The universe continues on like nothing has changed, because indeed, nothing has.

    Let’s take this issue from another angle. Say if you press a button, millions of people will be thrown into the pits of Hell to suffer forever. Obviously you would not press this button. The absence of pain here, though, is objectively neutral. Nobody exists to be saved of this horror. The universe continues on like nothing has changed, because indeed, nothing has. There is no sigh of relief, except by those already existing.

    Still, something seems a little funny. I will attempt to explain more:

    No sane individual will argue that it is not-bad to bring great suffering into existence. Quite clearly, we would be extremely guilty for throwing even just one person into the pits of Hell forever.

    But presumably we will also be willing to accept that it is a bad thing to exclude potential happy people from existence.

    -----

    Now for my more fleshed-out argument:

    I am of the opinion that, ceteris paribus, we have a duty to bring pleasure into existence. By itself, without any other variables, we have a duty to bring as much pleasure into existence. Of course, no scenario is without variables. To bring pleasure into existence would require me to do work and take time out of my own day (spent experiencing pleasure, myself). Since when do I have to ignore my own desires and give pleasure to other people?

    But again, there’s another catch. If my existence is acting as a preventative wall against pleasure, then I have a duty to eliminate my resistance. For example, say I park my car in the middle of an intersection (for no important reason), and there is a group of people trying to get across to get ice cream. I am preventing them from getting their ice cream. As a good fellow of society, it’s my duty to get out of the way so other people can experience pleasure, just as it’s other people’s duty to maintain a low resistance to other people’s desires (so long as they don’t conflict with their own non-harmful desires).

    In a nutshell, what this all means is that we have a duty, ceteris paribus, to not prevent (obstruct) the pleasure of other people, but we have no duty to give pleasure to these people (unless we have no more important obligations - namely, the pursuit of one's own desires).

    So let’s turn to the negative side, that of pain and suffering. It’s the mirror of pleasure. We have a duty, ceteris paribus, to not impose pain upon another individual. But we have no duty to prevent pain from being imposed upon another individual (unless we have no more important obligations - namely, the pursuit of one's own desires).

    -----

    Now, how do we evaluate obligations? Ta-dah! Consequentialism!

    If I’m a SWAT team member who has their vehicle in the middle of the intersection during an armed robbery at a bank, I am indeed preventing people wanting ice cream to get this ice cream. But I’m also preventing pain from occurring (in the bank), and since it’s my job as a hypothetical SWAT team member, I have a duty to prevent this suffering. The people wanting ice cream also have a duty to put aside their desires for ice cream for the greater good.

    If I’m a potential parent, wondering if I should have a child, then duties still apply. I have no obligation to bring pleasure into existence, because this would require me to set aside a ton of time and effort raising this child. But I do have an obligation to not bring pain into existence (unless for good reason), and birth is a completely unnecessary activity (spawned from the primal desires of people) and thus does not have good enough reasons to support its actualization.

    -----

    I’d also like to point out how this duty and calculus-based system recognizes heroism and sacrifice. To be a hero means to go beyond the expected duty for the sake of the greater good. And to be a sacrifice requires one to go beyond the expected duty for the sake of the greater good. Let’s look at some examples:

    Say I am the same SWAT team member during the bank robbery. Say I rush in courageously and save the bank, but in the process get shot in the leg. I would be a hero for doing this. This is typically why we see soldiers and rescue-workers as heroes (even if they haven’t done anything particularly heroic).

    Say I am a parent who brings a child into existence in a world in which not much suffering exists at all, perhaps just a few aches and pains and a few disappointments (if that). To bring such a child into this possible world of beauty and pleasure is not necessary at all, and yet I took time out of my life to raise this child and give them a pleasurable existence. Clearly, this is a (good) sacrifice because I could have abstained from having a child in this near-perfect world.

    But like most of you will probably sense, this world that we live in is not perfect. Suffering abounds. Pleasure is intrinsically contingent. The sacrifice of the parent is not really something to be praised, then. Although it is a sacrifice indeed, it’s also quite ethically dubious, as the parent would have imposed a sufficiently large amount of pain unto another person without the appropriate amount of pleasure.

    -----

    We have no way of knowing the exact amount of pleasure or pain experienced by a person. It’s entirely subjective and variant. But we can know that birth is ethically dubious by at least two ways (assuming my prior ethical stance):

    1.) Life has structural problems, chinks in its very being. Schopenhauer identified this to be the Will, Buddhists identify this as tanha, Cabrera identifies this as moral disqualification. We can also see how pleasure is not a fundamental structure to life – it is a contingent phenomenon that depends on the aforementioned structural issues.

    2.) We have a duty to take into account the worst case scenario. The worst case scenario, in this world at least, is always worse than the absence of the best case scenario. The best case scenario is not even remotely common or easy to obtain, while the worst case scenario is, in comparison, easier and far more common.

    -----

    I hope I have given an intuitive and easily-applicable ethical system, as well as a persuasive case for antinatalism.
  • Janus
    16.5k
    I would say you have no obligation to either bring pleasure to, or remove pain from, others, your obligation is only to refrain from (to the best of your knowledge and ability) removing their pleasure or bringing their pain.

    Of course this is not to say that you should not help someone who is suffering when it is within your power, or that you should not give someone what they want, if it is within your power to know what that is, as well as to give it to them, and if you judge that what they want will truly benefit them, and not harm others.

    You certainly have no right to bring millions of others into existence, regardless of whether it is to bring them to experience pleasure or pain.
  • Michael
    15.8k
    I hope I have given an intuitive [my emphasis] and easily-applicable ethical system, as well as a persuasive case for antinatalism. — darthbarracuda

    Is that what your argument rests on? An intuitive acceptance of your claim that we have a duty to not prevent pleasure and a duty to not impose pain?

    Or are these claims something that can actually be supported?
  • Sinderion
    27
    1) Why do you think morality is (at least partly) about consequences?
    2) Why do you think pleasure is good and pain is bad?
    3) In what sense is the problem with life "structural", given your responses to (1) and (2)?
  • _db
    3.6k
    I would say you have no obligation to either bring pleasure to, or remove pain from, others, your obligation is only to refrain from (to the best of your knowledge and ability) removing their pleasure or bringing their pain.

    Of course this is not to say that you should not help someone who is suffering when it is within your power, or that you should not give someone what they want, if it is within your power to know what that is, as well as to give it to them, and if you judge that what they want will truly benefit them, and not harm others.
    John

    That's why I mentioned ceteris paribus cases.

    You certainly have no right to bring millions of others into existence, regardless of whether it is to bring them to experience pleasure or pain.John

    I would argue that we have no right to bring millions of people into an existence of suffering, but we at the very least have no constraints upon bringing millions of people into an existence of pleasure. If these people go on to have an objectively good life, I see no reason to call this immoral. However we can't know if they will have a good life and we have to look at the worst-case scenario.
  • _db
    3.6k
    Is that what your argument rests on? An intuitive acceptance of your claim that we have a duty to not prevent pleasure and a duty to not impose pain?

    Or are these claims something that can actually be supported?
    Michael

    It's not that simple, obviously. We have a duty not to prevent pleasure as long as this does not create more pain, for example.

    I take it to be obvious that ethics is keenly related to intuitions, if not entirely formed from them.
  • _db
    3.6k
    1) Why do you think morality is (at least partly) about consequences?
    2) Why do you think pleasure is good and pain is bad?
    3) In what sense is the problem with life "structural", given your responses to (1) and (2)?
    Sinderion

    1) (At least partly), what we do is largely caused by our reasons, and our reasons tend to be a prediction of the future end-state.

    2) I take it to be a blunt primitive that what is good is what is pleasurable, and what is bad is what is painful.

    3) I would refer you to the various pessimistic philosophers.
  • Michael
    15.8k


    And if one person's intuitions differ from another's? Is there some way to determine who is right and who is wrong?
  • _db
    3.6k
    I don't think our intuitions vary to such a degree that we can't come to a unified consensus.
  • Michael
    15.8k
    So what of the pro-life, pro-choice debate?
  • _db
    3.6k
    Those who are in their respective camps aren't usually so steadfast that it's impossible to change their intuitions on things.
  • Michael
    15.8k


    Changing someone's intuitions? Sounds like an oxymoron. Intuitions are what people have before any reasoned examination.

    And what sort of reasoning would you use? What evidence supports the claim that some given thing is a duty?
  • Deleteduserrc
    2.8k
    This makes sense to me!

    It's hard to be an antinatalist when your friends are all having kids though :’(
  • Janus
    16.5k
    That's why I mentioned ceteris paribus cases.darthbarracuda

    I don't see how 'other things being equal' applies here. Can you explain?

    I would argue that we have no right to bring millions of people into an existence of suffering, but we at the very least have no constraints upon bringing millions of people into an existence of pleasure. If these people go on to have an objectively good life, I see no reason to call this immoral. However we can't know if they will have a good life and we have to look at the worst-case scenario.darthbarracuda

    But that's the whole point of why I said we have no right to intentionally bring millions of people into existence ( by mass-cloning, say?), because we cannot know whether their lives would be predominately pleasurable or painful.

    It's bad enough that we indulge in mass-breeding of animals!
  • _db
    3.6k
    The very process of philosophy is at least partly anchored on intuitions. We believe things because of reasons, and intuitions are often these reasons. If I can show you that one or more of your intuitions are wrong, then you will hopefully take my position. It's what I'm doing right now.
  • _db
    3.6k
    I don't see how 'other things being equal' applies here. Can you explain?John

    What I meant is that in an isolated, laboratory-like setting, we have a duty to give other people pleasure and take away their pain. This setting would make us omniscient, omnipotent, and not restricted by other things, such as our own desires. This is why we have an obligation to stop a child-kidnapping by an old man, but we don't have an obligation to immediately get involved in a child-kidnapping when the kidnapper is a physically-hefty giant of a man with a gun. All of these are variables that affect our judgement, and more often than not this judgement revolves around our own self-preservation.

    But that's the whole point of why I said we have no right to intentionally bring millions of people into existence ( by mass-cloning, say?), because we cannot know whether their lives would be predominately pleasurable or painful.

    It's bad enough that we indulge in mass-breeding of animals!
    John

    Right, we can't know this. But suppose we can know this. Then it would be, at the very least, morally good to bring people into good existences.
  • _db
    3.6k
    This makes sense to me!

    It's hard to be an antinatalist when your friends are all having kids though :’(
    csalisbury

    Shit, I accidentally flagged your post.

    Anyway thanks for the remark. I suppose it is difficult to remain an antinatalist while everyone else is having children. It's especially difficult when you know that most relationships you get into will end when you tell them you don't want children because of certain reasons.
  • Sinderion
    27
    Some fundamental beliefs are indeed intuitive. For instance, the intuition that other minds exists and that I am currently interacting with other minds doesn't seem rationally refutable, so long as I am genuinely arguing with another person. So, in some sense it seems like it is necessary, at least in the instance when I take myself to be arguing with another person, to hold that it is true that other minds exists. But the intuition about pleasure and pain isn't quite the same as that, nor the intuition that morality is about consequences. They aren't built into the definition of morality, nor are they necessary intuitions to hold for me to argue with you.

    So I'm not sure how you can be so certain about the intrinsic goodness of pleasure and pain, or that morality is fundamentally about consequences.
bold
italic
underline
strike
code
quote
ulist
image
url
mention
reveal
youtube
tweet
Add a Comment

Welcome to The Philosophy Forum!

Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.