Socrates: Well spoken. For even though your example is a thought experiment, it arises from the realm
of contingency: it depends on concrete circumstances—who hires whom, how many coins someone
carries—all things that do not follow from the essence of the matter, but from chance. But what comes from
chance is not necessary—and what is not necessary cannot be the object of knowledge. Therefore, Ed: your
example remains in the domain of the opinionable, because it aims at something that neither always is nor
is so by its own nature—but only through external conditions. And in this very point, it becomes clear that
it can never touch epistēmē in the sense of being. And can it surprise us, then, that logos fails when it seeks
to grasp what is not stable?14
I tend to see these sort of issues as indictive of the fact that "justified true belief" is simply a bad way to define knowledge. It's a definition that recommends itself by being analytically quite easy to work with; however this is a bit like the guy who lost his keys on the lawn and looks under the street light for them instead because "that's where he can see."
If knowledge involves the adequacy of the intellect to being, then simply affirming true propositions with proper discursive justification is not all there is to knowledge. Truth is primarily a property of the intellect, and only analogically predicated of linguistic utterances (as signs of truth in the intellect). When someone thinks p is true for bad reasons, and p is true, there is an adequacy of the intellect to being insomuch as truth is properly affirmed, but this will not involve the fuller adequacy that comes with understanding (which we would tend to call "knowledge.")
I think the empiricist tendencies in analytic thought tend to lead to a neglect of the role of understanding in knowledge. However, even if one dismisses any faculty of noesis/intellectus (which I wouldn't), I still think the phenomenology of knowledge suggests a big role for understanding (and this a relevant role for problems of vagueness). With vagueness, it seems we can have properly justified true belief and still lack "knowledge" in a strong sense. Knowledge is understanding and if "the truth is the whole," it is also in some sense inexhaustible. A "model" that tries to make truth primarily a binary property of propositions is going to miss this (and has other problems if truth/falsity represent contrary instead of contradictory opposition).
It seems to me like you are getting at the role of understanding in knowledge, which has a phenomenological component. If truth just involved discursive justification and assigning the right truth values to linguistic utterances or symbolic strings, then LLMs would "know," right? — Count Timothy von Icarus
This is precisely what Aristotle would say re episteme. The example relies on a coincidence of accidents. Could it be reconstructed with per se predication? I don't think I've ever seen it done.
The difficulty of limiting knowledge to being is of course explaining discursive knowledge in the realm of becoming, which does seem to exist. This requires a robust metaphysics, a "metaphysics of knowledge," which is made difficult by the tendency of modern thought to put either epistemology (early modern) or philosophy of language (linguistic turn) before metaphysics.
I would guess we have pretty similar opinions here. We had a recent thread on this and my thoughts were:
[... alllll the Text]
When we get to the "metaphysics of knowledge" I don't even know if it is appropriate to call knowledge (or at least what is most fully knowledge) a "belief." When we are sure that there are cars in the oncoming traffic lane and that we mustn't drive into them, I think this is not simply a case of sense data + ratio (computational reason) = propositional belief. The reason we find it quite impossible to ignore such knowledge lies, IMHO, more in the co-identity of knower and known in such cases (a union). People find it impossible to believe otherwise because their intellect is "informed" by truth in the senses (sense knowledge), or what we might call the communication of actuality.
That's a fairly Aristotlian/Neoplatonic view, and less strictly Platonic of course. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Imagine you believe Route A is the fastest way to work. You’ve taken it many times, it’s usually reliable, and today it gets you there quickly. But tomorrow, a construction site appears, traffic backs up, and Route B would have been faster. Your belief was reasonable — but only under yesterday’s conditions. — DasGegenmittel
The problem with knowledge is that it is used in a paradoxical way; we need a knowledge dualism. On the one hand, we say “I know” in cases where we can be certain that something is true, such as in mathematics. On the other hand, we use the same expression in situations involving contingency, like traffic routes. The underlying distinction is that some domains, like mathematics, involve elements that do not change—numbers, for example. The number 1 is always 1, without exception. — DasGegenmittel
Thus, we can even claim to have knowledge of things like current traffic conditions, which may be the best available to us so far, even if they don’t necessarily reflect reality. Since the world can change without our awareness, there can be no definitive knowledge about the future—only conceptual knowledge. — DasGegenmittel
One might object: “But we constantly experience that we do have knowledge!” However, this is a mistaken intuition, as illustrated by Gettier cases. The problem is what Popper also pointed out in the sciences: verification is a poor guide and a pathway to pseudo-science—or in our case, pseudo-knowledge. In dynamic environments, we can only corroborate, not verify. — DasGegenmittel
The problem isn’t that belief fails to endure — it’s that the justification isn’t connected to the truth-maker in a reliable way. The broken clock case isn’t a fluke: it’s a stand-in for many real-world scenarios where we reason well, but for the wrong reasons — and get it right only by chance. — DasGegenmittel
— just like the clock — DasGegenmittel
— just like the clock. — DasGegenmittel
This is my entire point. All of these examples fail to rise to something accepted into a functional system that would be called "knowledge". All of them dissolve under a short temporal arc. A diagnostic error is not medical knowledge, AI bias is in the context of how the computer believes complicates at best. Post rationalization of a stock trade isn't thought of as persistent justified belief. — Cheshire
No one has ever claimed that these cases constitute knowledge. The whole point of the Gettier problem is precisely that the definition is fulfilled, yet what we have still doesn’t count as knowledge in the way we expect it to. Ergo, JTB doesn’t work as a universal account of knowledge. — DasGegenmittel
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.