Cognitive relativism is a troubling thesis. Consider the point that it makes the concepts of truth, reality, and value a matter of what sharers in a form of life happen to make of them at a particular time and place, with other forms of life at other times and places giving rise to different, perhaps utterly different or even contrary, conceptions of them. In effect this means that the concepts in question are not concepts of truth and the rest, as we usually wish to understand them, but concepts of opinion and belief. We are, if cognitive relativism is true (but what does true now mean?), in error if we think that truth and knowledge have the meanings we standardly attach to them, for there is only relative truth, there is only reality as we, in this conceptual community at this period in its history, conceive it.
The reading of Wittgenstein which suggests that he takes such a view is consistent with much of what he otherwise says. For Wittgenstein the meaning of expressions consists in the use we make of them, that use being governed by the rules agreed among the sharers of a form of life. This presumably applies to expressions like true and real themselves and indeed, it is precisely Wittgenstein's point that such expressions cease to be philosophically significant once we remind ourselves of their ordinary employments. It follows that the possibility of there being other forms of life, even just one other, with different agreements and rules means therefore that each form of life confers its own meaning on true and real and therefore truth and reality are relative not absolute conceptions. This is a highly consequential claim.
Wittgenstein sometimes appears to be committed to cognitive relativism as just described. He says: "If a lion could talk, we could not understand him" (P II p.223); "We don't understand Chinese gestures any more than Chinese sentences" (Z 219). These remarks suggest relativism across "forms of life"; Wittgenstein may be saying that because meaning and understanding are based upon participation in a form of life, and because the forms of life in which, in their different ways, lions and Chinese engage are quite different from ours, it follows that we cannot understand them their view of things is inaccessible to us and vice versa. In On Certainty Wittgenstein appears to commit himself to relativism in a single form of life across time, by saying that our own language-games and beliefs change (C 65, 96#7, 256), which entails that the outlook of our forebears might be as inaccessible to us cognitively as is that of the lions or, differently again, the Chinese.
One need not take as one's target so radical a form of the thesis to show that cognitive relativism is unacceptable, however. This can be demonstrated as follows. Suppose that cognitive relativism is the case. How then do we recognize another form of life as another form of life? The ability to detect that something is a form of life and that it differs from our own surely demands that there be a means for us to identify its presence and to specify what distinguishes it from ours. But such means are unavailable if the other form of life is impenetrable to us, that is, if it is closed against our attempts to interpret it enough to say that it is a form of life. This means that if we are to talk of other forms of life at all we must be able to recognize them as such; we must be able to recognize the existence of behaviour and patterns of practices which go to make up a form of life in which there is agreement among the participants by reference to which their practices can go on. Moreover, if we are to see that the form of life is different from our own we have to be able to recognize the differences; this is possible only if we can interpret enough of the other form of life to make those differences apparent. And therefore there has to be sufficient common ground between the two forms of life to permit such interpretation.
This common ground has to involve two related matters: first, we have to share with the aliens some natural capacities and responses of a perceptual and cognitive type, giving rise to at least some similar beliefs about the world; and secondly we have to be able to share with them certain principles governing those beliefs; for one important example, that what is believed and therefore acted upon is held to be true. This has to be so because, as remarked, detecting differences is only possible against a shared background; if everything were different participants in one form of life could not even begin to surmise the existence of the other.
But this requirement for mutual accessibility between forms of life gives the lie to cognitive relativism. This is because the respects in which different forms of life share an experiential and conceptual basis which permits mutual accessibility between them are precisely the respects in which those forms of life are not cognitively relative at all. Indeed, cultural relativism, which is not just an unexceptionable but an important thesis, itself only makes sense if there is mutual accessibility between cultures at the cognitive level. Hence it would appear that the only intelligible kind of relativism there can be is cultural relativism.
Do you believe it's true that the earth orbits the sun? Did you know that this "truth" is relative to choices that we little people make? If there's no one to choose a frame of reference, there is no truth of the matter. This is not philosophy. It's physics. — frank
If there's no one to choose a frame of reference, there is no truth of the matter. This is not philosophy. It's physics. — frank
A good rule of thumb for everyone is to keep in mind that, during a conversation, if it just so happens that good common sense needs to be praised, then something about the conversation has gone terribly wrong. — Arcane Sandwich
Physics, not philosophy, suggests nothing is really true? — Count Timothy von Icarus
I understand the inscrutability of reference, and more generally the indeterminancy of translation to be more or less equivalent to contextualism as opposed to relativism, because semantic indeterminancy is a theory (for want of a better word) of meta-semantics that in effect considers the meaning of a proposition to be relative to the context of the agent who asserts the proposition, and hence the public inability to know what the speaker is referring to - as opposed to relativism that is a theory of truth that considers truth to be relative to the speaker. — sime
Well, what exactly is a concept? You won't find one by dissecting a brain. — Banno
So is a belief a thing, or a series of interconnected activities and ways of thinking? — Banno
It's true that the earth orbits the sun if we say the sun is stationary relative to the earth. We could instead pick the earth as the stationary point and then it wouldn't be true that the earth orbits the sun. — frank
This is not rocket science guys. — frank
Also energy and mass are constructs. — frank
They aren't observable. — frank
The list goes on. — frank
Oh, very much so. Nothing here should be construed as suggesting that there are no such thing as beliefs. And I'd even go along with reifying them, when we use them as explanations for actions, for example, so long as we are aware that this is what we are doing.The comparison to "concept" is good. Neither one can be reduced to physical items. But don't we agree that there's more to existing than being physical? — J
The Earth doesn't orbit around the sun, nor the sun around the earth, but both orbit around a common centre of mass, under the influence of the other bodies in the solar system; and this will be so regardless of the frame of reference chosen. — Banno
We moved to essences when ↪Count Timothy von Icarus made the suggestion that to "grasp the intelligibility of things" - gavagai, perhaps - we needed first intelligible essences... or something like that. There was an odd circularity here, in that we need essences to understand what something is, but when pressed it seems Tim thinks an essence is exactly what it is to understand what something is... we understand what something is by understanding what it is. Now circularity is not strictly invalid, but it is far from convincing. And there's the rejection of logical atoms, together with the analysis around family resemblance, amongst other things, for advocates of essence to deal with.
↪Count Timothy von Icarus seems now to be ascribing some form of cognitive relativism to someone - not sure if it's Quine, or @frank, or me, or all of us
Things are not words, and words are not things
At any rate, what constitutes the center of a star system or galaxy is not arbitrary. — Count Timothy von Icarus
There's a kind of absolutism that belongs to a theistic outlook. It's the kind of absolutism that would have a person deny something as simple as Galilean transformation. Meh. — frank
By trying to make sense of your post. For instance,I have no idea how you came to this take. — Count Timothy von Icarus
I didn't say that you said that essences is "what it is to understand something", rather that understanding what something is, involves understanding its essence. So ok, you think that "essences would be what is understood" but when asked what an essence is there is a gap; not properties, not definitions, but quiddity; and I have nothing left with which to understand quiddity except as "the inherent nature or essence of something". The circularity remains. As I said, not vicious, but not helpful in terms of explaining stuff.Things have essences. Our senses grasp the quiddity of things. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Well, your posts are erudite and expansive, but perhaps not so pertinent as they might be. Passive aggressive writing as an art form? Almost making an argument, but not quite, so as to maintain plausible deniability...No clue where you're getting that either. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Harking back to General Semantics, again? It's "The map is not the territory", and reminds us that any map is incomplete. Sound advice.The territory is not the map. — Arcane Sandwich
I don't read frank as suggesting that mass is not real. Quite the opposite. — Banno
Mass in modern physics has multiple definitions which are conceptually distinct, but physically equivalent. Mass can be experimentally defined as a measure of the body's inertia, meaning the resistance to acceleration (change of velocity) when a net force is applied.[1] The object's mass also determines the strength of its gravitational attraction to other bodies. — Wikipedia
In physics energy is not a substance, nor is it mystical. Energy is a number. A quantity. And the quantity itself isn’t even particularly fundamental. Instead, it’s a mathematical relationship between other, more fundamental quantities. It was 17th century polymath Gottfried Leibnitz who first figured out the mathematical form of what we call kinetic energy – the energy of motion. He realized that the sum of mass times velocity squared for a system of particles bouncing around on a flat surface is always conserved, assuming no friction and perfect bounciness. Leibnitz called this early incarnation of energy vis viva – the living force. — Matt O'Dowd
It has been said that “E = mc²” proves that physics has dematerialized matter. This claim involves two confusions: the identification of “matter” and “mass”, and the belief that energy is a thing, while actually it is a property of material things: there is no energy without things, just as there are no areas without surfaces. — Bunge (2012: 137)
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.