Harman rejects Whitehead’s relationalism for two reasons: 1) he worries it reduces ontology to “a house of mirrors” wherein, because a thing just is a unification of its prehensions of other things, there is never finally any there there beneath its internal reflections of others;
“The ontological structure of the world does not evolve…which is precisely what makes it an ontological structure” [GM, 24]
Why is it that people agree on so much? I think this comes down to how norms of judgement are generated. Peoples' eyes agree on object locations very durably, so location within a room works like that. Even if they might disagree on the true locations of objects when the rulers come out - like if my coaster is 30cm or 30.005cm from the nearest edge of my desk to me. If correct assertibility is an assay, truth is crucible.
When people share the same contexts, the overwhelming majority of conduct norms about such basic things are very fixed like that. That includes various inferences, like "if you put your hand in the fire, you'll burn it", "don't put your hand in the fire" comes along with that as the judgement that burning your hand in the fire for no reason is bad is very readily caused by the pain of it.
In the latter regard, there's a room for a moral realism in terms of correct assertibility, since the conventions are so durable and there's room to claim that "needless harm is bad" is true.
I'm not really sure what point you're trying to make. — Count Timothy von Icarus
A blanket renouncement of figurative language and metaphor? — Count Timothy von Icarus
I would say here: things cannot be figurative language and metaphor all the way down. Right?
When we read a book about insects or French history, do we only learn about words since that is all the books contain? — Count Timothy von Icarus
To be sure, there can be figurative language that is more or less empty, but it is not all empty. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Plato and Dante are two of the finest philosophers in history and both make extensive use of imagery and present their works in narratives packed with symbolism and drama. — Count Timothy von Icarus
They are successful, in part, not in spite of this technique but because of it. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Indeed, both suggest that what they most want to speak about cannot be approached directly, through syllogism and dissertation, but must "leap from one soul to another, as a flame jumps between candles." — Count Timothy von Icarus
IMO, one of the great losses in modern philosophy is its move away from drama and verse. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Nietzsche is a standout for this in our own epoch, — Count Timothy von Icarus
many of the older great works, from Parmenides, to Plato, to St. Augustine, to Boethius, to Dante, to St. John of the Cross to Voltaire are filled with it. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Camus and Sarte it seems, were not enough to start a trend. — Count Timothy von Icarus
I've only read one of Whitehead's books, but this does seem to be a problem for process philosophy in general. Of course, simply positing objects and essences does very little to fix the issue either. If the question: "why do some sorts of processes just happen to occur?" is problematic (which I'd agree it is), it seems the same sort of question would be problematic for objects, which was Srap's point earlier. — Count Timothy von Icarus
Harmon is "democratic" with his objects- what he calls "flat ontology". All objects are of equal weight as far as how relations are concerned. That is to say, all objects present a "vicarious/sensational causation" whereby one object is "translated" with another. Even if a log is burned, the log's essence is still withdrawn and ever-present in this theory. These even go down to non-physical objects like abstract concepts, fictional characters, and the like. They all have a unity, irreducibility, and can enter into relations with other objects. This allows for objects to persist beyond simply their reduced parts, or simply their relations/processes. As for the question, "Why these objects?", I am not sure his take other than it's a brute fact of his metaphysics. — schopenhauer1
In ordinary language, the word “object” denotes a material thing that can be seen and touched. By contrast, in modern philosophy “object” (objectum, Gegenstand) stands for whatever can be thought about: it applies to concrete things and abstract ones, arbitrary assemblages and structured wholes, electrons and nations, stones and ghosts, individuals and sets, properties and events, facts and fictions, and so on. The concept of an object is thus the most general of all philosophical concepts. — Mario Bunge (2010)
This book calls for what might be termed an object-oriented philosophy, and in this way rejects both the analytic and continental traditions. The ongoing dispute between these traditions, including the sort of “bridge building” that starts by conceding the existence of the dispute, misses a prejudice shared by both: their primary interest lies not in objects, but in human access to them. The so-called linguistic turn is still the dominant model for the philosophy of access, but there are plenty of others—phenomenology, hermeneutics, deconstruction, philosophy of mind, pragmatism. None of these philosophical schools tells us much of anything about objects themselves; indeed, they pride themselves on avoiding all naive contact with non human entities. By contrast, object-oriented philosophy holds that the relation of humans to pollen, oxygen, eagles, or windmills is no different in kind from the interaction of these objects with each other. For this reason, the philosophy of objects is sometimes lazily viewed as a form of scientific naturalism, since it plunges directly into the world and considers every object imaginable, avoiding any prior technical critique of the workings of human knowledge. But quite unlike naturalism, object-oriented philosophy adopts a bluntly metaphysical approach to the relations between objects rather than a familiar physical one. In fact, another term that might be employed for object-oriented philosophy is guerrilla metaphysics—a name meant to signify that the numerous present-day objections to metaphysics are not unknown to me, but also that I do not find them especially compelling. — Graham Harman (2005)
The so-called linguistic turn is still the dominant model for the philosophy of access, but there are plenty of others — Graham Harman (2005)
By contrast, object-oriented philosophy holds that the relation of humans to pollen, oxygen, eagles, or windmills is no different in kind from the interaction of these objects with each other. For this reason, the philosophy of objects is sometimes lazily viewed as a form of scientific naturalism, since it plunges directly into the world and considers every object imaginable, avoiding any prior technical critique of the workings of human knowledge. But quite unlike naturalism, object-oriented philosophy adopts a bluntly metaphysical approach to the relations between objects rather than a familiar physical one. — Graham Harman (2005)
I don't accept the pertinence of schools as presented here but do credit Harman for giving an excellent rant. — Paine
The carnival tent rustles in the evening breeze, disturbing the moods of those who approach. Inside the tent are swarms of humans and trained animals; there are jarring sounds, strange ethnic foods, and shadows. For a few moments the music of a concealed organ is countered by the rumble of thunder, as emaciated dogs begin to whine. A small fight breaks out, soon to be halted by a sneering, scar-faced man. Suddenly, hailstones strike the roof of the tent like bullets, frightening everyone: the visitors, the fortunetellers, the unkempt and corrupted security guards, the monkeys sparkling with costume jewelry. At long last, the organ player's morbid inner anger takes command, and he begins an atonal dirge that will last throughout the storm.
All of this can be explained by atoms. — Harman (2005)
About the remark about schools of thought? — Paine
I think this is significant. For the speculative realists, "correlationism" or the idea that the world cannot be accessed outside a human/animal perspective, is the enemy. — schopenhauer1
This is also important in understanding this metaphysics. In his particular flavor of speculative realism, it seems objects have ways of either translating or not translating their being to each other. I don't get though, how something fictional can be anything outside of a human interaction. — schopenhauer1
According to this theory, it would seem that even if humans were necessary for Gandalf to exist, once created, Gandalf is its own object, with its own withdrawn and mysterious essence that can only be translated with other objects, including humans. — schopenhauer1
Another oddity in the theory would be, if anything can be an object, what then would not count as an object? If Gandalf, the number 3, the type "dog", a particular dog named Rex, Narnia, Middle Earth, a subatomic particle, and a brown hat are all their own individual, essentialized, independent objects, what is not an object? — schopenhauer1
I have a problem with the encyclopedic approach to expression of ideas. Half of me roots for Harman's language while the other half objects to another victim of an accepted practice. — Paine
Said like an entry in a text that does not concern you. — Paine
Not really. Good ol' fashioned relationism poses a greater philosophical problem for speculative realism. — Arcane Sandwich
Besides, Meillassoux and Harman criticize correlationism for different reasons. They don't agree as to what it is that correlationism gets wrong. Meillassoux sees flaws where Harman sees virtues, and Harman sees flaws where Meillassoux sees virtues. — Arcane Sandwich
Not sure if this is correct, but if that's your theory, OK. — Arcane Sandwich
Qualities. For Harman, qualities are not objects, though he suggests that under certain conditions, a quality can become an object. But that's beside the point here, — Arcane Sandwich
Sensual Qualities - Real Qualities
Sensual Objects - Real Objects
These can be combined in many different ways. For example, a fictional character is a sensual object that has a real quality. Éowyn and Aragorn exists as sensual objects, not as real objects. However, they have real qualities, since, for example, they are copyrighted characters, you cannot use them in your own novel. That is in fact why the Tolkien foundation sued TSR (the old Dungeons & Dragons company) way back in the day. IIRC, a judge ruled that the word "hobbit" was copyrighted. So, instead of using the word "hobbit", TSR used "halfling". — Arcane Sandwich
Coupling Heidegger's tool analysis with the phenomenological insights of Edmund Husserl, Harman introduces two types of objects: real objects and sensual objects. Real objects are objects that withdraw from all experience, whereas sensual objects are those that exist only in experience.[30] Additionally, Harman suggests two kinds of qualities: sensual qualities, or those found in experience, and real qualities, which are accessed through intellectual probing.[30] Pairing sensual and real objects and qualities yields the following four "tensions":
Real Object/Real Qualities (RO-RQ): This pairing grounds the capacity of real objects to differ from one another, without collapsing into indefinite substrata.[31] This tension thus refers to "a real or indescribable object" encrusted with "real properties" that cannot be experientially understood.[32] Harman refers to this as "essence".[33]
Real Object/Sensual Qualities (RO-SQ): As in the tool-analysis, a withdrawn object is translated into sensual apprehension via a "surface" accessed by thought and/or action.[31] This tension thus refers to "the multiple facets [an object] displays to the outer world, and whatever [real, withdrawn] organizing principle is able to hold together [those] features."[34] Harman identifies this as "space".[35]
Sensual Object/Real Qualities (SO-RQ): The structure of conscious phenomena are forged from eidetic, or experientially interpretive, qualities intuited intellectually.[31] This tension thus refers to "a perfectly accessible [object] whose features are withdrawn from [total] scrutiny",[34] Harman dubs "eidos"[36]
Sensual Object/Sensual Qualities (SO-SQ): Sensual objects are present, but enmeshed within a "mist of accidental features and profiles".[37] This tension thus refers to "an enduring sensual object and its shifting parade of qualities from one moment to the next", which Harman identifies as "time".[38]
To explain how withdrawn objects make contact with and relate to one another, Harman submits the theory of vicarious causation, whereby two hypothetical entities meet in the interior of a third entity, existing side-by-side until something occurs to prompt interaction.[39] Harman compares this idea to the classical notion of formal causation, in which forms do not directly touch, but influence one another in a common space "from which all are partly absent". Causation, says Harman, is always vicarious, asymmetrical, and buffered:
— https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Object-oriented_ontology
It doesn't seem to be as much a problem except for Harman who focuses on objects contra process/qualities-only. — schopenhauer1
Meillassoux focused more on correlationism, and found that it kept people in an epistemic circle and thus "speculative realism" is an attempt to break it, philosophically. Harman agrees partly that correlationism has some truth to it as far as how humans relate to objects, but he democratizes it such that all objects have the ability, via vicarious causation to perceive to sense the object (i.e. sensual object), via the object's translated, sensual qualities (i.e. the qualities of an object as sensed by another object). A tree and wind have an interaction that is different than a tree and a human, for example. For Harman, relations are what matters. However, it is not all relations. It may even transform its appearance, but retains its essence (like the burned log). Each object, has an essence that is withdrawn or hidden, and thus retains its independence from complete reduction to its qualities, causal factors, or behaviors. — schopenhauer1
I am interpreting Harman, so not my own theory per se. — schopenhauer1
It's actually quite the point. If Gandalf is purely from human imagination, that would seem to undermine his attempt at saying objects have independence. Also, what is the mechanism that makes the object an object at that point? Why is it not then something else- an idea, an abstraction, etc. This then becomes a slippery slope whereby objects are so ill-defined as to not matter in any useful sense. — schopenhauer1
I think you are misapplying Harman's notion of sensual object/qualities here. Sensual qualities, as far as I see, are only tied with sensual objects. — schopenhauer1
Sensual objects are "tree-for-x" (human let's say). The sensual qualities would be the appearance of the tree-for-x (rough, brown, tall, etc.). The real object is the tree's essence which is withdrawn, independent of relations with other objects, and not fully comprehensible. The real qualities, might be things selected out as what composes the real object (but apparently never exhaustive), like the molecular structure let's say. Whatever form that particular tree takes in its relations with others, the essence always holds, though not fully knowable, though some real qualities can be picked out.
Thus Gandalf and Eowyn and Aragorn are always sensual objects with sensual qualities, as they are objects only ever relational to humans. — schopenhauer1
So what's your point here? It went over my head, if there was indeed a point to be made here. To me it sounds like you're just describing a state of affairs, and you're doing so in a neutral way. — Arcane Sandwich
I have published a paper where I say that for Harman, all ideas are sensual objects, but not all sensual objects are ideas. He doesn't say that himself, but in one of the emails that he sent me, he seemed to agree with what I said about him on that specific point. — Arcane Sandwich
You'd be wrong. A real object can have sensual qualities, just as a sensual object can have real qualities. There's an article that Harman himself published in response to one of my own articles. In my article, I press him on the topic of hobbitsvis a vis the topic of matter, and he explicitly says, in print, that hobbits are sensual objects that have real qualities, and that the same is true of matter, in his view. — Arcane Sandwich
Then you're argument is with Harman himself, not with my interpretation of his philosophy. — Arcane Sandwich
And that would be true, but are you defending Harman with these objections or do you see them as well? — schopenhauer1
My sentiments on Harman's philosophy (and he knows this himself, since we've been exchanging emails for almost 10 years now) are mixed, precisely because I'm a materialist and he is not, and because I endorse scientism and he does not. He values science, but he places no stock in scientism. I, on the other hand, place stock in both. Despite these differences, Harman and I are realists. So there is important common ground there. And there are many more similarities and differences, but those that I just mentioned would be the core differences between us. — Arcane Sandwich
Interesting. I rarely see people "embrace" the label "scientism". What is that definition for you? — schopenhauer1
But as far as what I brought up, do you know of his answers, or would you have a defense? Specifically I am talking about how and when something becomes an object. — schopenhauer1
(...) For me, of course, all change is purely sensual, and involves shifting qualities. What I think happens is not change, but composition or synthesis between previous separate entities. (...) — Harman (personal communication)
It seems like a Deus ex machina to say Gandalf is thus an object. Is Gandalf an object at the first thought of a Gandalf-like character? The name Gandalf? The writing of pen to paper about Gandalf? The neural connections? It just seems oddly misplaced to call it an object even with the appellate "sensual". It also has to me, obvious connections to the essentialism of Kripke in Naming and Necessity, and Putnam with ideas of scientific kinds. Does Gandalf obtain in all possible worlds? Etc — schopenhauer1
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.