If we want to make use of a real radical consideration of subjectivity, each of us must consider his own subjectivity in the “here and now” of the moment when he is thinking. This is the true consideration of subjectivity, that is able to demolish any idea of truth, be it universal or not. If I take into consideration my subjectivity here and now, I realize immediately that I have no way to give any kind of guarantee about what I am thinking of, what I am talking about. — Angelo
Could there perhaps be confusion between psychological and epistemological certainty? Psychological certainty is how confidently I believe something. Epistemological certainty is how justified I am in believing it. Both pertain to the subject who believes, as opposed to the object of belief. Now psychologically, I feel quite confident about many things. But then, when philosophical thought puzzles are posed, my confidence may be more or less undermined, depending on how I react to pondering them. But I can be well justified in believing something even if my psychological feeling of certainty is very low, and I can be very poorly justified in believing something even if my psychological feeling of certainty is very high.
So what constitutes a good enough justification for a belief that one can be epistemologically certain that it is true? I would say I can be epistemologically certain of a belief if it follows logically from other beliefs of which I am epistemologically certain. But if I don't have foundational beliefs of which I am epistemologically certain, an infinite regress would ensue. So I would say that a belief is foundational if it is indispensable. And a belief is indispensable if it cannot be denied without undermining all my other beliefs. For instance, the belief in the principle of non-contradiction is indispensable because, if I deny it, then all my other beliefs may be true and false at the same time, in which case I can't really believe anything.
I would say that the belief that your knowledge extends beyond the here and now is indispensable. Yes, if all you knew were the here and now, you could not guarantee anything. For knowledge requires justification, and justification requires thought, and thought requires time. If I think something is true at this moment, then I must have justified it at some point in the past, otherwise I'd have no reason to believe it true. But if I only knew the here and now, I'd have no way of knowing whether I'd justified any of my beliefs in the past, in which case I'd have no reason to believe any of my beliefs were true. So memory must be at least somewhat reliable. For if memory were totally unreliable, then I'd have no way of knowing anything.
Objective reasonings give us the illusion of being working, just because we forget ourselves in the moment we describe them.
This might be used as an argument against my conclusion about the contradiction I showed in my preceding message: since I can’t guarantee the correcteness of what I said, I can’t be sure that what I described was really a contradiction. But this makes me think that other people must be in the same condition: how can they guarantee that their reasoning is free from errors? How can they be less uncertain than me? — Angelo
I think you may be sneaking a pinch of naive skepticism into your argument. Because you're claiming to believe two things 1) I am in this condition where certainty is impossible, and 2) since I am in this condition, others probably are as well. Either you're claiming 1 and 2 to be true or at least probable propositions, in which case you are guilty, I think, of naive skepticism. Or, you are just attempting to express your subjective experience of considering philosophical ideas, and you are not stating propositions which you believe are worthy of rational assent. What else could you be doing?
What is important now is that I ended up in questions, not in statements. Who will be able to put a stop to our questioning, our doubting?
Relativism and scepticism can be attacked if they are considered as sources of statements: “nothing is absolute”, “nothing can be known”. But I think that their real nature is questioning, doubting, without giving nor suggesting any answer. — Angelo
This sounds more like a spiritual practice than a philosophical position. In fact, I've heard that ancient skepticism, along with other ancient schools of philosophy, was a spiritual practice. As a skeptic, you refuse to give assent to any propositions, and instead you question and doubt everything proposed to you. Rather than seek out things to believe, you seek out reasons to undermine belief, and your goal is to believe as little as you can, ideally nothing. Or, perhaps that's not the main goal of your life, but it is your goal when you philosophize. Either way, I would call that kind of skepticism a spiritual practice, not a philosophical position, because it describes a way of life as opposed to a set of propositions to believe. Skepticism may be your way of life, or, more likely, it is not your way of life, but only the way you like to do philosophy. You may even selectively apply skepticism to some philosophical problems but not to others. For instance, you may be a skeptic when discussing metaphysics but a rigid dogmatist when discussing politics (I suspect that a lot of people on this site are like that, although perhaps you aren't).
If you have chosen to pursue skepticism as a way of life, I doubt I can convince you to stop by means of philosophical argumentation, because the whole point of skepticism is to undermine philosophical arguments. In fact, there's nothing really incoherent about believing nothing, although I suspect that most people who call themselves skeptics do believe in some things. But I think that the mission of skepticism is diametrically opposed to the mission of traditional philosophy. Philosophy, traditionally conceived, is love of wisdom, and wisdom, traditionally conceived, involves knowledge, especially knowledge of important truths that are fundamental to understanding reality and human life. Philosophy pursues knowledge of these truths by means of rational argumentation, and it argues by means of propositions that can be either affirmed and believed or denied and disbelieved. Since the style of skepticism you are proposing seems to replace affirmation and denial with perpetual doubt and propositions with endless questions, I think it falls outside the realm of philosophy. You can engage with a philosopher as a skeptic, but your mission as a skeptic is not the same as the philosopher's mission. He seeks truth, you do not. He uses argumentation to discover what ought to be believed, you use argumentation undermine all beliefs.
1) At the beginning they trust memory and logic;
2) they just apply logic
3) and they discover that the application of logic demolishes trust in memory and, as a consequence, in logic as well;
4) then they become skeptic.
What is demolished by the application of logic is the initial trust on memory and logic, because this initial trust is the necessary base that makes possible the conclusion. — Angelo
If memory skepticism really could be demonstrated from undeniable premises, then I suppose I'd have to assent to it, and, as a result, fall into radical skepticism. But once a radical skeptic, I'd have no reason to remain as such or not to remain as such. However, I think you're right that, if it is logically demonstrable that memory cannot be trusted, and human logic (by human logic, I just mean the ability of humans to use logic and trust that it leads to truth) depends on memory, then it is demonstrable that human logic cannot be trusted. And if it is demonstrable that human logic cannot be trusted, then it is unreasonable to believe in anything. Human logic would then be like a defective machine that conked out every time you tried to use it. It's not that 'belief in logic is unreasonable' would be a reasonable proposition. Rather, the very attempt to construct reasonable propositions would lead to self-contradiction and absurdity. Does this sound right? Is that what you're saying?
That's all true, assuming memory skepticism is demonstrable. But I don't think it is. I think it's perfectly reasonable to think it self-evident that memory is generally trust-worthy. Or, if I were, for instance, suffering from alzheimer's, and my memory was impaired, I would know my memory was impaired. But it may be self-evident that I was not, for instance, created one moment ago. That seems fairly self-evident to most non-philosophers. And even if you doubt it, I don't think you can prove that it's not self-evident. And since all our beliefs rely on memory, I can perhaps assert truly 'either memory is self-evidently at least somewhat trustworthy, or human knowledge is impossible'.
I think that you reach the conclusion that skepticism is self-refuting because you consider the question as everything happening in the same instant, like in a photo, while instead it is a sequence of reasoning steps that happen over time, by stages, like a film. — Angelo
I think your argument works insofar as it shows that, if having beliefs entails contradiction, it is unreasonable to believe anything. But then, once the conclusion is accepted, it must also be rejected, since if I believe that's it's unreasonable to believe anything, then this belief is also unreasonable. If reason is like the machine that conks out when you try to use it, you just have to stop using it. If you're computer conks out when you turn it on, you can't use your computer to look up what's wrong with your computer. In the same way, if logic refutes itself, you can't use logic to prove that one should be a skeptic. All you can do is observe logic refuting itself. So, to use your film analogy, you can observe logic undermining itself during the part of the film when logic is still in use. But then once you advance to the part of the film when logic has already been undermined, you can no longer use it to show that logic undermines itself. Yes, the argument unfolds in time, but no, you, as a temporal being, cannot step outside the time in which the argument unfolds and simultaneously assert both the premises the conclusion. Once reach the conclusion, all you have left of the premises is your subjective reaction to having watched logic undermine itself. You can't continue to assert the premises once you've accepted their conclusion, which undermines all premises. You don't have a logical argument to justify your disbelief in logic. You could rewind to the part where logic undermined itself and watch it again. But once it happens, you have to go back to believing nothing. I think Wittganstein puts this well when he says (roughly) that once you climb the ladder and stand on the higher, philosophical ground, you have to kick away the latter.
So, back to the proposition 'either memory is self-evidently at least somewhat trustworthy, or human knowledge is impossible': you cannot reasonable maintain that human knowledge is impossible. However, I see no reason why you can't reasonably maintain that memory is self-evidently at least somewhat trustworthy.
Here's one other possible argument against memory skepticism: change seems to be perceived, and one cannot perceive change without perceiving multiple instances of time. But if one perceives multiple instances of time, one must experience both past and present, because the present constitutes only a single moment, and the future cannot be perceived. And the perception of the past is memory. So it is self-evident that we have memory at least of the previous moment. But in the previous moment, we also remembered the moment before that. So we can at least remember the previous two moments. This argument cannot be infinitely repeated, for the further we recollect back in time, the more vague our memories become. Maybe the argument only works to prove that I remember the previous 10 seconds. Perhaps it doesn't work at all. I haven't thought about it much. But I suspect that other arguments against memory skepticism could also be formulated.