Olsen's conclusion is not quite right, but not quite wrong, either. We are, after all, aware of the Müller-Lyer Illusion, and after a point no longer surprised by it - one might say it becomes a part of the way we think. The Müller-Lyer Illusion is part of the world around you and part of what you think. Olsen's conclusion, "the world around you is not the way you think it is", is imprecise, as are similar views expressed already in this thread.Here’s the thing: Even after we have measured the lines and found them to be equal and have had the neurological basis of the illusion explained to us, our conscious awareness still perceives one line to be shorter than the other. One can know that the two lines are the same length whilst at the same time experience them as different lengths.This has a serious effect on our conception of the nature of experience.
The world around you is not the way you think it is. — Zach Olsen
Yep. I supose that what is salient here is that sometimes folk doubt what they are experiencing without good reason. Austin is slowly and carefully showing why this is problematic.Sometimes there is reason to doubt what you're experiencing... — frank
The invalidity of this is apparently not obvious to many. Stove's gem, the worst argument in the world, and so on.We sometimes see things incorrectly; therefore, we never see them correctly. — javi2541997
Austin is certainly not making any such claim. Sometimes we see things that are real. It does not follow that everything we see is real. Sometimes we see things that are not real. It does not follow that everything we see is not real. So your "For the realists, there is no room to say anything more on the perception than a chair is chair" is a mischaracterisation. Nor is memory a simple process of storage. I suggest the brush you are using here is too broad. If for you "the realist's account on perception sounds too simple", you might consider that you have not represented their view accurately.If everything you perceive is real... — Corvus
:up: Slowly...“seeing” a table is to identify something as a table — Antony Nickles
To be clear, there's no need to leave Wittgenstein out, indeed there is much to be gained in keeping him in, but we need to take care, given the considerable overlap, as to who is claiming what.I’ll leave him out of it; — Antony Nickles
The danger here is the presumption that what we perceive is all of one sort, in such a way that we can apply the label "sense data" in all cases. Austin is showing that this is not a good idea.It would be reasonable to introduce a term like sense-data as a place-holder for whatever it is we decide we perceive directly. — Ludwig V
Some might now replace "sense datum" with "qualia". Not quite the same. — Banno
Is that what he addresses in a somewhat racist fashion on p.26? I don't think he's saying that there is only one correct way, but that there is at least one correct way, that does not involve sense data. And that's all he need show in order to undermine Ayer's contention that we are obligated to invoke sense data. Ayer's argument is based on there being no alternative. Austin simply need show one alternative.Austin sounds as if he believes there’s only one correct way to see something.. — J
But my biggest puzzle is what would count as direct perception. — Ludwig V
And the answer here is simply that there is no problem with a straight stick that looks bent when partially immersed in water, not illusion, no delusion, nothing that needs explaining beyond the physics of optics mentioned earlier. And there certainly is no need to infer the existence of a novel entity to take on the part of being what we see when we look at a straight stick that appears bent when partially submerged, appart form and distinct from the stick.What is wrong, what is even faintly surprising, in the idea of a stick's being straight but looking bent sometimes? Does anyone suppose that if something is straight, then it jolly well has to look straight at all times and in all circumstances? — p.29
for though, as Ayer says above, 'it is convenient to give a name, to what he is experiencing, the fact is that it already has a name-a mirage. — p.32
The invalidity of this is apparently not obvious to many. Stove's gem, the worst argument in the world, and so on. — Banno
And when you see yourself in a mirror, there is no need to invent a simulacrum to stand in for you. There is no illusion, no hallucination and no error. What you see is yourself, reflected in the mirror. Again, this is what mirrors do, and no further explanation is needed that replaces your reflection with anything immaterial. — Banno
Such as something wrong with our ability to perceive anything at all (which we should also keep in mind is only one example of philosophies desire to create a problem as one kind of thing, as with: appearances, beliefs, subjective, morality, etc.) — Antony Nickles
rather than what Austin is doing here which is to examine how our failings are varied and thus have various ordinary ways in which we account for them. — Antony Nickles
Yes, it is simplistic. But what makes it invalid is that the conclusion does not follow from the premise.I personally think that it is invalid because it is simplistic — javi2541997
What is not ruled out here is the possibility that we sometimes see things incorrectly and at other times we see them correct. That is, the premise does not ruled out that we sometimes see things correctly.We sometimes see things incorrectly... — javi2541997
This just does not follow....therefore, we never see them correctly — javi2541997
That's a good question, with a long, but not so difficult, answer. I don't know your philosophical background. So I will go back a few steps. What follows is a potted history, and as such it is roughly correct in broad outline, but definitely wrong on the detail.But do we see ourselves in the mirrors because this is what they do - reflecting - or because do we actually exist? — javi2541997
what we imagine direct perception would be the perfect case of. So if we set aside the problem of direct or indirect, — Antony Nickles
The danger here is the presumption that what we perceive is all of one sort, in such a way that we can apply the label "sense data" in all cases. Austin is showing that this is not a good idea. — Banno
Instead it starts pretty well where we are, here and now. And it proceeds by looking with great care at the philosopher's main tools, their words. — Banno
and there's a mention of Gellner's book here:-Some mirth has been found in Austin's use of "the ordinary man" - as if such as he would have any idea.. — Banno
Ernest Gellner. In his book, Word and Things, — Richard B
I'm afraid I'm a bit confused about whether we are working through the sections systematically or just reading the book at our own pace? — Ludwig V
I would prefer the thread stay on the topic and not become another diatribe against linguistic philosophy. It's probably inevitable that it become so mired, but I'll not help out. Much.
As for your specific question, I don't see Gellner's "four pillars" at all in Austin; indeed, Austin's method is antagonistic to all four. — Banno
Austin is certainly not making any such claim. Sometimes we see things that are real. It does not follow that everything we see is real. Sometimes we see things that are not real. It does not follow that everything we see is not real. So your "For the realists, there is no room to say anything more on the perception than a chair is chair" is a mischaracterisation. Nor is memory a simple process of storage. I suggest the brush you are using here is too broad. If for you "the realist's account on perception sounds too simple", you might consider that you have not represented their view accurately. — Banno
My problem is that I can't imagine what direct perception would be. Isn't this part of what we need to recognize here? If nothing could count as direct perception, then the idea that perception is actually indirect doesn't make sense. The problem is the move from "some perception is indirect" to "all perception is indirect".
The “directness” describes the relationship between perceiver and perceived. By “direct” one means there is no causal intermediary between the perceiver and the rest of the world, that we aren’t viewing sense-data, neurons, shadows on a cave wall, but the things themselves. — NOS4A2
My problem is that I can't imagine what direct perception would be. Isn't this part of what we need to recognize here? If nothing could count as direct perception, then the idea that perception is actually indirect doesn't make sense. The problem is the move from "some perception is indirect" to "all perception is indirect". — Ludwig V
But I agree that setting this issue aside enables us to understand what is going on here better, even though I'm not entirely sure that the last word has been said here. (I have in mind Cavell's idea that the idea of a last word on scepticism is a mistake.) — Ludwig V
Does such a position [with qualia] involve believing in sense-data? — J
Austin, of course, has been the butt of many jokes, the quintessential irrelevant Oxford Don, putting the anal back into analytic, and so on. — Banno
Austin intimates somewhere, all perception is direct. — NOS4A2
As I mentioned earlier, the argument from illusion is intended primarily to persuade us that, in certain exceptional, abnormal situations, what we perceive—directly anyway—is a sense-datum; but then there comes a second stage, in which we are to be brought to agree that what we (directly) perceive is always a sense-datum, even in the normal, unexceptional cases.
P.44
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.