1. P; that is being.
2. not P; that is not being.
3. P and not P; that is being and that is not being.
4. not (P or not P); that is neither being nor that is not being.
These four statements hold the following properties: (1) each alternative is mutually exclusive (that is, one of, but no more than one of, the four statements is true) and (2) that all the alternatives are together exhaustive (that is, at least one of them must necessarily be true) — Wikipedia
Then the wanderer Vacchagotta went to the Blessed One and, on arrival, exchanged courteous greetings with him. After an exchange of friendly greetings & courtesies, he sat to one side. As he was sitting there he asked the Blessed One: "Now then, Venerable Gotama, is there a self?"
When this was said, the Blessed One was silent.
"Then is there no self?"
A second time, the Blessed One was silent.
Then Vacchagotta the wanderer got up from his seat and left.
Pyrrho the skeptic would've found Nagarjuna's tetralemma very useful, no? — TheMadFool
The use of these mood functions also facilitates something superficially resembling the motivations for non-classical types of logic such as paraconsistent logics and intuitionist logics, without actually abandoning the principle that differentiates classical logic from them: the principle of bivalence. The principle of bivalence is the principle that every statement must be assigned exactly one of two truth values, "true" or "false", no more and no less. Intuitionist logics allow for statements to be assigned neither of those truth values, while paraconsistent logics allow for statements to be assigned both of them at the same time.
With these mood functions, similar things can be constructed without actually violating the principle of bivalance, because there is nothing strictly logically prohibiting it being the case that neither is(P) nor is(not-P), if for example P were some kind of descriptively meaningless statement; it is merely necessary, to preserve bivalance, that either is(P) or not(is(P)), but not(is(P)) doesn't have to entail that is(not-P). Similarly, there is nothing strictly prohibiting it being the case that be(P) and be(not-P), if for example there were some morally intractable situation where both P and not-P were required, and so any outcome was unacceptable; it is merely necessary, to preserve bivalence, that either be(P) or not(be(P)), but not(be(P)) doesn't have to entail be(not-P).
Fleshing out the philosophical implications of things like descriptively meaningless claims and morally intractable situations is a topic for further discussion. But in any case a logic of this form is in principle capable of discussing things that are, in a loose sense, "both true and false" or "neither true nor false", without technically violating the principle of bivalence. — Pfhorrest
for example P were some kind of descriptively meaningless statement — Pfhorrest
eternalism — Wayfarer
Pyrrho doubted that he doubted — Gregory
A conversation I had with a Buddhist — TheMadFool
I did one of the 10-day Vipassana courses some time back.
Rule no 1: no conversation.
For very small windows of opporunity, you were allowed to talk to the supervising teacher about questions, doubts, discomfort (of which there was plenty) but never about 'philosophy'. — Wayfarer
I got that information from the skepticism section on historyofphilosophy.net — Gregory
It was never put in those dry scholastic terms in the early Buddhist texts. — Wayfarer
By and large, Kaccayana, this world is supported by a polarity, that of existence and non-existence. But when one sees the origination of the world as it actually is with right discernment, "non-existence" with reference to the world does not occur to one. When one sees the cessation of the world as it actually is with right discernment, "existence" with reference to the world does not occur to one. — Wikipedia entry ‘Two Truths’
Yeah but, however 'judgment p' is sliced & diced, in principle, sufficient grounds are required to warrant any assent, doubt or dissent; otherwise, in practice, all propositional stances are just arbitrary (idle). This critical insight is usually / traditionally missed in discussions of Pyrrho (and, given his Indian influences, I assume 'sufficient grounds' is also a feature of Nagarjuna's tetralemma ... though I've not studied him or his "school" anywhere near enough to be confident about that). See Peirce (re: fallibility), Dewey (re: inquiry) & Witty (re: doubt) for further developments of 'non-relativist' 'non-antirealist' 'non-nihilistic' 'woo woo-free' skepticism.Given any proposition p, there are 4 possible states it can be in, yes p, no p, yes p and no p, snd neither yes p nor no p.
1. p (yes p)
2. ~p (no p)
3. p &~p (yes p & no p)
4. ~(p v ~p) (neither yes p nor no p)
Nagarjuna calls them the 4 extremes. He negates them all
1. p: not p
2. not p: not not p
3. (p & ~p): not (p & not p)
4. ~(p v ~p): not ~(p v ~p) — TheMadFool
Some English translation equivalents of wú or mu 無 are:
"no", "not", "nothing", or "without"
nothing, not, nothingness, un-,
is not, has not, not any
Pure human awareness, prior to experience or knowledge. This meaning is used especially by the Chan school
A negative.
Caused to be nonexistent
Impossible; lacking reason or cause
Nonexistence; nonbeing; not having; a lack of, without
The 'original nonbeing' from which being is produced in the Tao Te Ching. — Wikipedia
Assuming E = the buddha exists after death.
1. E. No!
2. Not E. No!
3. E and not E. No!
4. Neither E nor not E. No! — TheMadFool
I wouldn't mind seeing something a bit more concrete than this obviously self-refuting edict.
Have you a proper citation? — Banno
Also see Graham Priest on Nagarjuna (Aeon Magazine). — Wayfarer
...and your opinion of this view? — Banno
Get involved in philosophical discussions about knowledge, truth, language, consciousness, science, politics, religion, logic and mathematics, art, history, and lots more. No ads, no clutter, and very little agreement — just fascinating conversations.