Am I? What language was that quote originally written in? If one is to be a literalist about this, then one has to take into consideration the fact that the passage in question was not really written in English. And whatever word was originally used there, it most certainly was not etymologically related to the Latin word Ratio.
Mystics would disagree
It only places the word of the Bible at odds with the word of science.
"Yes" to both questions.
Sure, because of the sheer number of scribbles and rules for putting them together in strings, not because of some special power of the scribbles have apart from representing things that are not scribbles. When communicating specifics, do the scribbles invoke more scribbles in your mind, or things that are not just more scribbles, but things the scribbles represent? To represent specifics you must already be able to discern the specifics the scribbles represent. Do the names of new colors for crayons create those colors, or do they refer to colors that we can already discern?
I didn’t say a coastline or an ant didnt exist until painted.
The word coastline implies a particular sense of meaning, and there are as many senses of meaning for it as there contexts of use.
Animals who interact with a coastline produce their own senses of meaning for it , even though they don’t perceive it in terms of verbal concepts.
Yes, this is not how I would phrase the issue myself, but I "get your point", so to speak. What I would say, is that if the catholicity of reasons exists (and if catholicity simpliciter exists), then it pre-dates the foundation of the Catholic church. Catholicity, if it exists, existed before the Catholic church existed. That's what I would say. And if this is so, then it follows that the Catholic church does not, and cannot, have a monopoly on catholicity. Which is why one can be a catholic outside the Catholic church. Agree or disagree? I feel like you disagree with me on this specific point, among others
Yes, it is. At the end of the day, it is
For example, I have blind faith in my feet, in the sense that I completely trust them when I absent-mindedly step up and walk towards the kitchen.
I feel like that's not sound reasoning on your part. It seems like you are appealing to the majority. Kierkegaard is in the minority here, sure. But that doesn't mean that he's necessarily wrong. Majorities can make mistakes, especially interpretative mistakes. That's why there is a literal use of the language to begin with: so that there are no interpretative mistakes, you just read what it says.
then I would ask: What is God testing here in the first place, if not Abraham's faith?
not the one who tries to rationalize what God is,
And that is exactly the sort of discussion that I point to, when I say that things cannot be metaphors and figurative language all the way down.
Then why should anyone listen to Christ instead of Epicurus? For Epicurus also had a concept of friendship.
Is this what you call "the catholicity of reason"?
I would say: there are many truths, they are not sui generis, and they are not potentially contradicting truths. In Henological terms: There are Many Truths, and none of them contradict each other. Contradictions only arise in Opinion (Doxa), not in Episteme.
Kierkegaard also pointed out (and rightly so) that God gave Abraham a fideist order when he ordered him to sacrifice his son. Do you disagree with that?
The account is interpreted as the drama of faith as opposed to the natural affections, a drama that applies to the reader (Origen). Not only is Isaac a figure of Christ in the Spirit, but also the ram symbolizes Christ in the flesh (Origen, Ambrose). Even Chrysostom abandons his customary moralizing and employs a typological interpretation. That Isaac was a type and not the reality is seen in the fact that he was not killed (Caesarius of Arles). Readers are also invited to interpret the story spiritually and apply it to themselves, so as to beget a son such as Isaac in themselves (Origen).
Things cannot be poetry and figurative language all the way down.
Why? That's exactly what it is. Believe, so that you might understand. It's a conditional statement: if P, then Q. In this case, the antecedent is Believe, just that, Believe, and that is 100% fideist. It's absolute blind faith, without an ounce of reason to it.
Can you explain it to me in simpler terms, please?
How would we know when one was correct?
The word ‘bus’ implies a system of interactions with the object ‘bus’ based on our understanding of what it is and what it does. Someone who doesnt know about automobiles or even carriages would see it as very different kind of object and interact with it in different ways as a result. If you want to see how different people interact differently with the same coastline ask them to sit down and paint a painting of the scene as accurately as possible. There will be similarities among the paintings, but none will look identical. This is not just due to different skill levels but to the fact that each person’s procedure for measuring and depicting it makes use of a slightly different process. Objective space is derivative of our subjective determination of space.
It depends on the system of convictions that underlie your beliefs concerning what is good and what is bad for a baby, just as what constitutes genital mutilation depends on such guiding assumptions. Archeologists found tiny tools and weapons dating back 1700 years.
If one thinks a brain is a physical organ that generates perceptual events, then it has to be explained how it is possible that these events can be about objects in the world.
But I said it is far worse. If causality cannot deliver "knowledge about" this means ALL that stands before me as a knowledge claim--explicit or implicit, a ready to hand pragmatic claim or a presence at hand (oh look, there is a cat) claim, or just the general implicit "claims" of familiarity as one walks down the street---requires something entirely other than causality to explain how it is possible.
But the above seems plainly false for the only way for an exemplification to exemplify is assume a particular causal series that demonstrates this. This is rare, and when it comes to a causal matrix of neurons and, synapses and axonal connectivity, well: my cat in no way at all "is exemplified" by this.
Kierkegaard didn't believe in the catholicity of reason, he was a protestant from Denmark. He was essentially a Christian Viking, from a theological POV. That's why he emphasizes irrationality (i.e., "berserk") and the knight of faith (i.e., "berserk-er").
For him, you mean? Or for anyone in general? If it's the latter, then I agree with Kierkegaard on this point: how do we even know that human reason has catholicity? It could just be secular universality for all we know.
What do you think of Tertullian's (or whoever "really" said it): Credo quia absurdum, "I believe because it is absurd."?
To say that America has a coastline is to assume some configurative understanding of what a coastline is, which is to say, a system of anticipations concerning what it means to interact with it.
whenever we use the word we commit ourselves to a particular implied system of interaction
Alicia Juarrero explains:
Nor should the meanings of these examples be reified as epistemological truths, as G.E. Moore tried to do when he attempted to demonstrate an epistemological certainty by raising his hand and declaring ‘I know that here is a hand’.
You’re doing the same thing by asserting with bold certainty ‘ a knife is a bad toy to give a baby!’ , ‘one can't mate a penguin and a giraffe!’ and ‘ one cannot take flight by flapping one's arms vigorously like a bird’! Are these certainties that need to be justified, and if so, is there an end to justification, a bedrock of belief underlying their sense and intelligibility? And what kind of certainty is this bedrock?
Scientific advances in understanding gravity, mass and energy from Newton to Einstein changed the meaning of these concepts in subtle ways. The notion of coastline doesnt exist independently of the actual processes of measuring it, and these processes conformist conventions of measurement.
Complex dynamical systems approaches applied to cognitive intentionality explain how intentional stances produce specific constraints, constants which do not act
as efficient causes.
But think about this re Socrates. I believe he'd dispute it vigorously
I also take MacIntyre's idea that we've lost the meaning of classical terms to exemplify this. The assumption seems to be a kind of "one word, one meaning" theory, so that if A comes along and says,"I'd like to use 'virtue' and 'essence' in the following ways" (giving cogent reasons, we'll assume), B replies, "No, you can't, for that is not what 'virtue' and 'essence' mean."
But st the same time , the laws and properties that we ‘discover’ in nature are not external to the ways we arrange and rearrange our relations with that world as knowledge
develops.
Or did you really think a human brain was some kind of mirror of nature? A brain and its "sensory equipment"--a MIRROR? Let's see, the electromagnetic spectrum irradiates this grass, and parts are reflected while others absorbed, and what is reflected is received by the eye and is conditioned by cones and rods and sent down the optic nerve and....now wait. Have we not entirely lost "that out there" in this?
One basic, but ignored premise must come to light: there is NOTHING epistemic about causality.
Rather, when an encounter with an object occurs, it is an event, and must be analyzed as such. What lies "outside" of this event requires a perspective unconditioned by the perceptual act, which is impossible. Unless you actually think that the world intimates its presence to a physical brain...by what, magic? Just waltzes into the brain and declares, here I am, a tree! I assume you do not think like this.
Kierkegaard knew very well about this problematic, for he had read Aristotle, Augustine, Kant, Hegel, and so on (he was, of course, literally a genius). One must know in the first place in order to acknowledge the "collision" between reason and existence. Reason cannot, keep in mind, understand what it is, cannot "get behind" itself (Wittgenstein). for this would take a pov outside outside of logic itself and this cannot be "conceived".
I don't know what Kant means by unknowable things-in-themselves. What is knowledge then if not something independent of the thing itself? You're assuming that there is more to know about something, when it could be possible that a finite number of sensory organs can access everything there is to know about other things. In fact, there are many characteristics of objects that overlap the senses. You can both see, hear and feel the direction and distance of objects relative to yourself. All three senses confirm what the other two are telling you. Having multiple senses isn't just a way of getting at all the propertied of other objects but also provide a level of fault tolerance that increases the level of certainty one has about what they are perceiving.
You can also depend on the process of causation in a deterministic universe as providing another level of certainty. Effects carry information about their causes. You can get at the cause by making multiple observations over time and finding the patterns. This allows you to predict with a higher certainty the cause of some effect you experienced. When billions of people use smart phones everyday, almost all day, and 99% of them work as intended, does that not give you a certain level of certainty that your smartphone will work today? Can we be 100% certain? No. Are we more than 0% certain? Yes, depending on the case. You seem to be maintaining that we can only every be 0% certain of anything.
To illustrate this, suppose we have three mostly identical systems involving three identical subjects having identical experiences of seeing an apple. In one case, the apple is whole. In another case, the apple has been carefully hollowed out. In a third, the apple is fake, plastic, but it appears indiscernibly similar to the real apples. In this example, we would say all three systems have the same B-Minimal properties because they produce the same phenomenal experience. Another way of thinking about this is that the B-minimal properties associated with any given interval of experience could be said to correspond to a set of possible P-regions, different physical ensembles that give rise to the same experience. Our experiences have a direct correspondence to some of the object/environment’s properties, just not all of them.
But now consider a longer interval of experience where a person sees an apple, walks up to it, picks it up, and takes a bite of it. The B-minimal properties of a system giving rise to this experience must be quite different. It is no longer the case that the hollowed-out apple or the
plastic one will be indiscernible from the real apple in these scenarios. As we can see from this example, the subject’s interaction with the environment affects the B-minimal properties required to produce their experience. When we move to an interval where the subject bites into the apple, the B-minimal properties must now be such that they can produce not only the sight of the apple, but the feeling of weight it produces in our subject’s hand, its taste and its smell.
One way to think of this interaction might be to say that the set of possible P-regions that have the B-minimal properties required to produce our subjects' experiences has been reduced by their walking up to the apple and taking a bite of it. In the case where the subjects merely looked at the apple, we just needed something that looked indiscernibly like a given apple from a fixed angle to produce the experience. In the second scenario, we need something that looks the same from different angles, feels the same, and tastes the same.
As we interact with objects in our environment, using more of our senses, we greatly reduce the number of possible physical systems that could give rise to our experiences.xiii In turn, the one-to-one correspondence between the B-minimal properties that act as the supervenience base for our experiences and our experiences comes to apply to a narrower and narrower set of possible physical systems (set of P-regions), and we come closer to uniquely specifying the properties of the objects we interact with.
Now consider what happens when we conduct scientific experiments, using finely tuned instruments that allow us to probe the properties of objects. In such cases, there is an even greater reduction in the number of possible P-regions that are consistent with the experiences of the experimenter. Moreover, we can consider what happens when a vast number of people are involved in such experiments, leading to a very large number of such experiences. As we consider more and more experiences, there appear to be fewer and fewer ways “the world could be” and still produce the same experiences investigators are having.
Such an insight does not, of course, rule out radical skepticism. We could still suppose that such experiences might be the product of some “simulation” or an “evil demon” à la Descartes. Yet representationalists generally allow that our experiences do have something to do with the world. Indeed, their claims are often based on findings in the sciences. Rather, they claim that the relationship between our experiences and the properties of objects is too indirect and dynamic to allow for true knowledge of those things.
Rather, we're trying to shake up a very common assumption among philosophers, which is that there is some sort of binding action (I called it "metaphysical Superglue" elsewhere) that makes a word inseparable from its object or meaning or concept -- take your pick of these imprecise terms. ("Cannot be grounded in any infallible a priori knowledge," in the words of the SEP article.)
Does this help us understand the relation of word and object, which I believe is Quine's point with "gavagai"? Not a rhetorical question -- you may well be seeing something here that I'm not.
There may well be. Rodl devotes an entire chapter to discussing Nagel's "view from nowhere," and one of his criticisms is this problem of the "loss of the viewer" -- what it does to 1st person propositions.
So leave it.
Which other targets of jihad are you talking about?
Sort of. Since the example concerns two linguistic communities who don't yet share a common translation for "gavagai", what else besides behavior would we have to go on?
I read him rather as using the gavagai story to show why the word/meaning pair is problematic.
These views of Quine and Davidson have been well received by analytic philosophers particularly because of their anti-Cartesian approach to knowledge. This approach says knowledge of what we mean by our sentences and what we believe about the external world, other minds, and even ourselves cannot be grounded in any infallible a priori knowledge; instead, we are rather bound to study this knowledge from a third-person point of view, that is, from the standpoint of others who are attempting to understand what we mean and believe. What the indeterminacy of translation/interpretation adds to this picture is that there can never be one unique, correct way of determining what these meanings and beliefs are.
I don't think that's the problem. Rules of math and logic are also extremely general principles, but we don't have trouble finding agreement there.
I'll go a step further and suggest that we have overwhelming agreement as to what is true and what is good.
The stuff we focus on is the stuff about which we disagree. That misleads some to think that we disagree about stuff. But our agreement about what the world is like is overwhelming. And our agreement about what things folk ought and ought not do is pretty broad, too.
Nothing does more for Jihadism, and brings more to its cause, than its oppression.
Is this your belief too?
How would we demonstrate that this is the case? It also seems kind of circular: claiming that the absolute encompasses all reality and appearances, doesn't it take for granted what it is supposed to establish?
Are you saying that our fixer knows they can, but doesn't believe they can?
The point here to work through the various ways in which "I know" is used? it would be prejudicial to supose that any was paradigmatic.
suggests that Wittgenstein had the contestable view that knowledge is the very same as belie
But one must surely believe what one knows? "I know it's raining, but I don't believe it!" is ironic? A play on our expectations?
He’s being a little sarcastic, in my reading, but his meaning is clear: If we continue to allow p to float somewhere in the World 3 of abstracta, without acknowledging its dependence on thought1, we are going to get a lot of things wrong.
If “the I think accompanies all our thoughts” has been rendered uncontroversial, is it now also uninteresting, unimportant? This is a further question, which I’m continuing to reflect on.
For example, judging that Obama lives in Chicago and judging that I correctly judge that Obama lives in Chicago are not two distinct judgments. This is just one act of judgment, which is at once a judgment that Obama lives in Chicago and a judgment that I correctly judge that Obama lives in Chicago. Often the adverb "correctly" (also "validly" or "rightly") drops out, and Rödl frames the self-consciousness of judgment as the idea that judging that p and judging that I judge that p are not distinct. For example, he says that "the act of the mind expressed by So it is is the same as the one expressed by I think it is so" (6). In any case, the thought is that one cannot pry apart the judgment that things are so and the judgment that I (correctly) judge that things are so. When I judge that Obama lives in Chicago, in that very act of judgment, I also judge that I (correctly) judge that Obama lives in Chicago.
I hate to say it, but a great deal of this comes down to how we want to use very ordinary words like "thought" and "accompany."
They are not equivalent.
2. Where do we find Wittgenstein claiming that knowledge is justified true belief?
1. Where in the grammar of ordinary language do we find the idea that knowledge is justified true belief?
You implied - stated - that Wittgenstein, and analytic approaches generally, equate belief and knowledge. That is not so.
Wittgenstein certainly did not equate knowledge and belief. He consistently takes knowledge to be both believed and true, and spends much effort in working through what else is needed.
Truth does not require justification. A proposition may be either true or not true, regardless of its being justified, known or believed.
I would say here: things cannot be figurative language and metaphor all the way down. Right?
...neither are all things unutterable nor all utterable; neither all unknowable nor all knowable. But the knowable belongs to one order, and the utterable to another; just as it is one thing to speak and another thing to know.
Saint John of Damascus - An Exposition of the Orthodox Faith
In their second chapter Gaius and Titius quote the well-known story of Coleridge at the waterfall. You remember that there were two tourists present: that one called it 'sublime' and the other 'pretty'; and that Coleridge mentally endorsed the first judgement and rejected the second with disgust. Gaius and Titius comment as follows: 'When the man said This is sublime, he appeared to be making a remark about the waterfall... Actually ... he was not making a remark about the waterfall, but a remark about his own feelings. What he was saying was really I have feelings associated in my mind with the word "Sublime", or shortly, I have sublime feelings' Here are a good many deep questions settled in a pretty summary fashion. But the authors are not yet finished. They add: 'This confusion is continually present in language as we use it. We appear to be saying something very important about something: and actually we are only saying something about our own feelings.'1
Before considering the issues really raised by this momentous little paragraph (designed, you will remember, for 'the upper forms of schools') we must eliminate one mere confusion into which Gaius and Titius have fallen. Even on their own view—on any conceivable view—the man who says This is sublime cannot mean I have sublime feelings. Even if it were granted that such qualities as sublimity were simply and solely projected into things from our own emotions, yet the emotions which prompt the projection are the correlatives, and therefore almost the opposites, of the qualities projected. The feelings which make a man call an object sublime are not sublime feelings but feelings of veneration. If This is sublime is to be reduced at all to a statement about the speaker's feelings, the proper translation would be I have humble feelings. If the view held by Gaius and Titius were consistently applied it would lead to obvious absurdities. It would force them to maintain that You are contemptible means I have contemptible feelings', in fact that Your feelings are contemptiblemeans My feelings are contemptible...[/i]
...until quite modern times all teachers and even all men believed the universe to be such that certain emotional reactions on our part could be either congruous or incongruous to it—believed, in fact, that objects did not merely receive, but could merit, our approval or disapproval, our reverence or our contempt. The reason why Coleridge agreed with the tourist who called the cataract sublime and disagreed with the one who called it pretty was of course that he believed inanimate nature to be such that certain responses could be more 'just' or 'ordinate' or 'appropriate'to it than others. And he believed (correctly) that the tourists thought the same.The man who called the cataract sublime was not intending simply to describe his own emotions about it: he was also claiming that the object was one which merited those emotions. But for this claim there would be nothing to agree or disagree about. To disagree with "This is pretty" if those words simply described the lady's feelings, would be absurd: if she had said "I feel sick" Coleridge would hardly have replied "No; I feel quite well."
When Shelley, having compared the human sensibility to an Aeolian lyre, goes on to add that it differs from a lyre in having a power of 'internal adjustment' whereby it can 'accommodate its chords to the motions of that which strikes them', 9 he is assuming the same belief. 'Can you be righteous', asks Traherne, 'unless you be just in rendering to things their due esteem? All things were made to be yours and you were made to prize them according to their value.'10
What's an example of an organism choosing its motives, goals, or purposes? Aren't those things we discover rather than determine?
You wrote that humans are reflexively aware of themselves. This aligns with the notion of subjectivity as consciousness, and consciousness as self-consciousness ( S=S). When God was believed to be the origin of all things, he-she was deemed as the true being, the basis on which to understand all other beings. When man eclipsed god, subjectivity and consciousness took on this role of true Being. An object is that that which appears before a positing self-affecting subject.
A different way to think about being is articulated by people like Heidegger. When he says that Dasein is the being who cares about his own existence, he is rejecting the notions of
subjectively as identity, as self-reflective awareness (S=S), in favor of the notion of being as becoming , as practical action. Being as thrownness into a world. This is consistent with Pierre-Normand‘s suggestion that the appearance of subjectivty ‘emerges from the co-constitution of the animal/person with its natural and social environment, or habitat and community.’
If it cannot, then my argument that only humans and other living organisms can change their normative motives, goals and purposes would seem to fail. But I would argue that this way of thinking assumes a split between psycho-social and biological processes, ontogeny and phylogeny, nature and culture. It is now understood that behavior feeds back to and shapes the direction of evolutionary processes directly through its effect of genetic structures. This means that the biological brain-body architecture organizing human motives, norms and purposes exists in a mutual feedback loop with cultural behavioral processes. Each affects and changes the other over time. The same is true of the machines we invent, but in a different way. We produce a particular A.I. architecture, and the spread of its use throughout culture changes the nature of society, and sparks ideas for innovations in A.I. systems.
But notice that human intelligence functions as interactive coping in contextually specific circumstances as an intrinsic part of a wider feedforward-feedback ecology that brings into play not only our reciprocal exchanges with other humans but also other animals and material circumstances. Machine ‘intelligence’, by contrast, does not participate directly in this ecological becoming. There is no true mutual affecting taking place when we communicate with ChatGPT. It is a kind of recorded intelligence, a dynamic text that we interpret, but like all texts , it is not rewriting itself even when it seems to respond so creatively to our queries.
Harman rejects Whitehead’s relationalism for two reasons: 1) he worries it reduces ontology to “a house of mirrors” wherein, because a thing just is a unification of its prehensions of other things, there is never finally any there there beneath its internal reflections of others;
“The ontological structure of the world does not evolve…which is precisely what makes it an ontological structure” [GM, 24]
Why is it that people agree on so much? I think this comes down to how norms of judgement are generated. Peoples' eyes agree on object locations very durably, so location within a room works like that. Even if they might disagree on the true locations of objects when the rulers come out - like if my coaster is 30cm or 30.005cm from the nearest edge of my desk to me. If correct assertibility is an assay, truth is crucible.
When people share the same contexts, the overwhelming majority of conduct norms about such basic things are very fixed like that. That includes various inferences, like "if you put your hand in the fire, you'll burn it", "don't put your hand in the fire" comes along with that as the judgement that burning your hand in the fire for no reason is bad is very readily caused by the pain of it.
In the latter regard, there's a room for a moral realism in terms of correct assertibility, since the conventions are so durable and there's room to claim that "needless harm is bad" is true.